2015
DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2015.1119413
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Historical Inductions: New Cherries, Same Old Cherry-picking

Abstract: Abstract. In this paper, I argue that arguments from the history of science against scientific realism, like the arguments advanced by Kyle Stanford and Peter Vickers, are fallacious. The socalled "Old Induction," like Vickers', and the so-called "New Induction," like Stanford's, are both guilty of confirmation bias, specifically, of cherry-picking evidence that allegedly challenges scientific realism, while ignoring evidence to the contrary. I also show that the historical episodes Stanford adduces in support… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
15
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
3
3

Relationship

2
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 20 publications
(15 citation statements)
references
References 41 publications
0
15
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In that respect, it is important to point out that, as I have argued elsewhere, historical inductions, both old, such as Larry Laudan's pessimistic induction (Mizrahi 2013a), and new, such as Stanford's NIS (Mizrahi 2015), are weak inductive arguments. The problems with these historical inductions are that they tend to commit the fallacy of biased statistics (Park 2011), they are based on unrepresentative samples (Fahrbach 2011), and the inductive samples they are based on are typically cherry-picked rather than randomly selected (Mizrahi 2013a).…”
Section: -64)mentioning
confidence: 87%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…In that respect, it is important to point out that, as I have argued elsewhere, historical inductions, both old, such as Larry Laudan's pessimistic induction (Mizrahi 2013a), and new, such as Stanford's NIS (Mizrahi 2015), are weak inductive arguments. The problems with these historical inductions are that they tend to commit the fallacy of biased statistics (Park 2011), they are based on unrepresentative samples (Fahrbach 2011), and the inductive samples they are based on are typically cherry-picked rather than randomly selected (Mizrahi 2013a).…”
Section: -64)mentioning
confidence: 87%
“…Excluding mere logical possibilities, how many "equally well-confirmed and scientifically serious alternatives" (Stanford 2006, p. 44) are there to theories of inheritance, or electricity, or magnetism? A few (Mizrahi 2015), but certainly not so many as to make it impossible to justifiably believe (though not "prove" in the strict sense, as Sterpetti seems to demand) that T has no "equally well-confirmed and scientifically serious alternatives" (Stanford 2006, p. 44). 14 In light of the above, then, it is not clear what Sterpetti has gained from turning Stanford's NIS from an inductive argument over the history of science to a deductive argument (specifically, a reductio).…”
Section: Setting the Record Straight: Inductive Vs Deductive Argumentsmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Recently, P. Kyle Stanford (2001Stanford ( , 2006 has developed what may be characterized as a new version of the PMI: … I propose the following New Induction over the History of Science: that we have, throughout the history of scientific inquiry and in virtually every field, repeatedly occupied an epistemic position in which we could conceive of only one or a few theories that were well-confirmed by the available evidence, while subsequent history of inquiry has routinely (if not invariably) revealed further, radically distinct alternatives as well-confirmed by the previously available evidence as those we were inclined to accept on the strength of that evidence. (Stanford 2001, S8-S9) The problem of unconceinved alternatives as an argument against scientific realism has been criticized on various grounds (e.g., Chakravartty 2008, Devitt 2011, Mizrahi 2015, but my goal here is just to note that the discussion of Section 3 can be extended to this new version of the PMI, which can be construed as follows: P(i) In the past time of theory 1, theory 1 was successful but there were unconceived alternative theories that were as well supported by available evidence but with radically different ontology. P(ii) In the past time of theory 2, theory 2 was successful but there were unconceived alternative theories that were as well supported by available evidence but with radically different ontology.…”
Section: Extension To the Problem Of Unconceived Alternativesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…My goal is to contribute to a growing literature that is critical of historical inductions such as the pessimistic (meta-)induction (PMI) argument (Poincaré 1952, 160;Putnam 1978, 25;Laudan 1981) and the problem of unconceived alternatives (Stanford 2001(Stanford , 2006 against scientific realism, concentrating mostly on the former. The PMI can be construed in different ways (Mizrahi 2015, Wray 2015, viz., as a deductive reductio ad absurdum (e.g., Psillos 1996Psillos , 1999, a counterexample to the no miracles argument and inference to best explanation argument for scientific realism (e.g., Saatsi 2005, Laudan 1981), or, usually, as an inductive argument (e.g., Poincaré 1952, Putnam 1978, Laudan 1981, Rescher 1987. In the following I will argue against the inductive version of PMI-or any construal of the PMI that makes use of historical induction-using John D. Norton's material theory of induction (Norton 2003, Manuscript).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%