2013
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-013-0139-1
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Truth promoting non-evidential reasons for belief

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
16
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
4
4
1

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 25 publications
(16 citation statements)
references
References 23 publications
0
16
0
Order By: Relevance
“…22 For arguments that there aren't epistemic values that call for promotion, see Littlejohn (2018). For a defence of an opposing view, see Talbot (2014). While I think that there might be a sense in which epistemic norms are sensitive to considerations about value (and hence might be thought of as teleological), the relevant values might not be ones that call for promotion.…”
Section: What Should Pro We Believe?mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…22 For arguments that there aren't epistemic values that call for promotion, see Littlejohn (2018). For a defence of an opposing view, see Talbot (2014). While I think that there might be a sense in which epistemic norms are sensitive to considerations about value (and hence might be thought of as teleological), the relevant values might not be ones that call for promotion.…”
Section: What Should Pro We Believe?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…5 For discussions of trade-offs and their (ir)relevance to epistemic status, seeFirth (1981),Jenkins (2007), andLittlejohn (2012). For sophisticated responses to such concerns, see Ahlstrom-Vij and Dunn (2014),Singer (2018), andTalbot (2014).6 This view is compatible with the view that a thinker's evidence ultimately determines what a thinker should believe. We can represent the evidentialist as someone who thinks that what we ought to believe is determined by what we have sufficient evidence to believe.…”
mentioning
confidence: 96%
“…Jonathan Matheson (2015: 145 ff.) calls the type of considerations that arise from this ‘instrumental epistemic reasons’; Brian Talbot (2014) calls them ‘truth-promoting non-evidential reasons for belief’; Kirk Lougheed and Robert Simpson (Forthcoming) call them ‘indirect epistemic reasons’. It seems plausible that such considerations can at least sometimes be regarded as reasons for belief of some sort, and so perhaps in a case like DETECTIVES an agent could appeal to them to resolve the pragmatic deadlocks I've adverted to.…”
Section: The Limitations Of Standards-based Permissivismmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Brian Talbot, in defending a form of epistemic consequentialism that's complementary to our position here, rejects Adler's view on this matter. For Talbot, reasons generated by indirect epistemic considerations and reasons grounded in routine appraisals of evidence can exert their normative force on people's beliefs in harmony with one another, insofar as both kinds of reasons ultimately derive from, and operate in the service of, the same epistemic ends (Talbot (2014), 615–616) 21 . Although we're sympathetic to this suggestion, we also think it makes matters sound implausibly smooth and simple.…”
Section: Taking Account Of Indirect Epistemic Reasons As Reasons For mentioning
confidence: 99%