2016
DOI: 10.1017/s0034412516000202
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Indirect epistemic reasons and religious belief

Abstract: If believing P will result in epistemically good outcomes, does this generate an epistemic reason to believe P, or just a pragmatic reason? Conceiving of such reasons as epistemic reasons seems to lead to absurdity, e.g. by allowing that someone can rationally hold beliefs that conflict with her assessment of her evidence's probative force. We explain how this and other intuitively unwelcome results can be avoided. We also suggest a positive case for conceiving of such reasons as epistemic reasons, namely, tha… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
6
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
2

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 11 publications
(6 citation statements)
references
References 32 publications
0
6
0
Order By: Relevance
“…17 This particular intrinsic/extrinsic distinction is inspired by Steel (2010), though I develop it differently. Lougheed and Simpson (2017) propose a similar distinction. 18 Several philosophers have pointed to considerations that I think are extrinsic epistemic reasons, e.g., McKinnon's (2015) "distal" epistemic considerations.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 88%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…17 This particular intrinsic/extrinsic distinction is inspired by Steel (2010), though I develop it differently. Lougheed and Simpson (2017) propose a similar distinction. 18 Several philosophers have pointed to considerations that I think are extrinsic epistemic reasons, e.g., McKinnon's (2015) "distal" epistemic considerations.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 88%
“…This particular intrinsic/extrinsic distinction is inspired by Steel (2010), though I develop it differently. Lougheed and Simpson (2017) propose a similar distinction.…”
mentioning
confidence: 91%
“…As noted above, for example, Christians believe in the final judgment and a future life in heaven after death, and Muslims believe that they will spend eternity with Allah in the hereafter. These examples illustrate how people can believe in concepts that extend into the future for nonevidence-based reasons (Longheed & Simpson, 2017). People can hold religious or political beliefs without any explicit awareness of their structure in a manner similar to how they can use language without metacognitive awareness of its grammatical rules (Claessens et al, 2020).…”
Section: Social Consequences Of Conceptual Beliefsmentioning
confidence: 97%
“…Jonathan Matheson (2015: 145 ff.) calls the type of considerations that arise from this ‘instrumental epistemic reasons’; Brian Talbot (2014) calls them ‘truth-promoting non-evidential reasons for belief’; Kirk Lougheed and Robert Simpson (Forthcoming) call them ‘indirect epistemic reasons’. It seems plausible that such considerations can at least sometimes be regarded as reasons for belief of some sort, and so perhaps in a case like DETECTIVES an agent could appeal to them to resolve the pragmatic deadlocks I've adverted to.…”
Section: The Limitations Of Standards-based Permissivismmentioning
confidence: 99%