2016
DOI: 10.1016/j.jet.2015.09.002
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Robust virtual implementation under common strong belief in rationality

Abstract: Bergemann and Morris (2009b) show that static mechanisms cannot robustly virtually implement non-constant social choice functions if preferences are sufficiently interdependent. Without any knowledge of how agents revise their beliefs this impossibility result extends to dynamic mechanisms. In contrast, we show that if the agents revise their beliefs according to the forward-induction logic embedded in strong rationalizability, admitting dynamic mechanisms leads to considerable gains. We show that all ex-post… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 16 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 29 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…24 Artemov et al ( 2013) analyze robust virtual implementation with respect torationalizability in static mechanisms. Mueller (2016) applies strong rationalizability to dynamic mechanisms. Bergemann and Morris (2016 and references therein) apply to static mechanisms the solution concept without belief restrictions and call it "belief-free rationalizability."…”
Section: ;M Imentioning
confidence: 99%
“…24 Artemov et al ( 2013) analyze robust virtual implementation with respect torationalizability in static mechanisms. Mueller (2016) applies strong rationalizability to dynamic mechanisms. Bergemann and Morris (2016 and references therein) apply to static mechanisms the solution concept without belief restrictions and call it "belief-free rationalizability."…”
Section: ;M Imentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In particular, Morris (2005, 2009a, b) study belief-free implementation in static settings, respectively in the partial, full, and virtual implementation sense. The belief-free approach has been extended to dynamic settings by Müller (2016) and Penta (2015). Penta (2015) considers dynamic mechanisms in environments in which agents may obtain information over time, and applies a dynamic version of rationalizability based on a backward induction logic (Penta 2011).…”
Section: Related Literaturementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Penta (2015) considers dynamic mechanisms in environments in which agents may obtain information over time, and applies a dynamic version of rationalizability based on a backward induction logic (Penta 2011). Müller (2016) instead considers virtual implementation via dynamic mechanisms, in the same (static) belief-free environments as Bergemann and Morris (2009b), using a stronger version of rationalizability with forward induction. Thanks to the stronger assumptions on the belief revision policy, he shows that dynamic mechanisms weaken the conditions for virtual implementation.…”
Section: Related Literaturementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Therefore, motivated by the Wilson doctrine(Wilson (1985)),Bergemann and Morris (2009, 2011) among others, relax the common knowledge assumption, and adopt a belief-free approach to study when and how a social choice function is fully implementable under all type spaces, which is the robust implementation problem.Most of the solution concepts studied under the interim implementation or robust implementation literature have been non-cooperative. For example,Postlewaite and Schmeidler (1986),Palfrey and Srivastava (1987, 1989), andJackson (1991) adopt the solution concept of Bayesian Nash equilibrium Bergemann and Morris (2009, 2011), Penta (2015,Müller (2016),. andOllár and Penta (2017) among others study rationalizable implementation or Bayesian Nash implementation under all type spaces.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Some other papers impose specific updating rules when Bayes' rule fails, e.g.,Penta (2015) andMüller (2016).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%