2021
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-021-01671-8
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Rational supererogation and epistemic permissivism

Abstract: A number of authors have defended permissivism by appealing to rational supererogation, the thought that some doxastic states might be rationally permissible even though there are other, more rational beliefs available. If this is correct, then there are situations that allow for multiple rational doxastic responses, even if some of those responses are rationally suboptimal. In this paper, I will argue that this is the wrong approach to defending permissivism -there are no doxastic states that are rationally s… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2023
2023
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
3
1
1

Relationship

1
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 7 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 55 publications
(51 reference statements)
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…14 Though see Matheson & Milam (2021) for an argument against the existence of non-moral blame. 15 See Li (2019) and Siscoe (2022) for a discussion of whether epistemic supererogation can provide support for epistemic permissivism, the view that there can be more than one rationally permissible belief which one may hold in relation to some body of evidence. 16 Those unconvinced by this example may consider the following example suggested by Nado (2019): "[S]uppose that I check ten separate sources before resting content with my belief that Mogadishu is the capital of Somalia.…”
Section: Epistemic Supererogationmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…14 Though see Matheson & Milam (2021) for an argument against the existence of non-moral blame. 15 See Li (2019) and Siscoe (2022) for a discussion of whether epistemic supererogation can provide support for epistemic permissivism, the view that there can be more than one rationally permissible belief which one may hold in relation to some body of evidence. 16 Those unconvinced by this example may consider the following example suggested by Nado (2019): "[S]uppose that I check ten separate sources before resting content with my belief that Mogadishu is the capital of Somalia.…”
Section: Epistemic Supererogationmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For a similar argument (about epistemic rationality, not fittingness) seeSiscoe (2022).15 This exposition elides the distinction between partial absolute gradable adjectives like "wet," which are associated with scales with minimal endpoints, and total absolute gradable adjectives like "empty," which are associated with scales with maximal endpoints. If "fitting" is an absolute gradable adjective, it is of the latter variety.16 It's worth noting that Berker and Maguire seem to agree that the natural-language term 'fitting' is gradable; Maguire simply insists that the property of fittingness is non-gradable.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…If "fitting" is an absolute gradable adjective, it is of the latter variety.16 It's worth noting that Berker and Maguire seem to agree that the natural-language term 'fitting' is gradable; Maguire simply insists that the property of fittingness is non-gradable. 17Burnett (2017: 70-2) defends this model at length; for philosophical work friendly to this model, seeHawthorne and Logins (2021),Siscoe (2022), andUnger (1979, ch. 2).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%