2012
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-012-0029-y
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

What time travelers cannot not do (but are responsible for anyway)

Abstract: The Principle of Alternative Possibilities is the intuitive idea that someone is morally responsible for an action only if she could have done otherwise. Harry Frankfurt has famously presented putative counterexamples to this intuitive principle. In this paper, I formulate a simple version of the Principle of Alternative Possibilities that invokes a course-grained notion of actions. After warming up with a Frankfurt-Style Counterexample to this principle, I introduce a new kind of counterexample based on the p… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1

Citation Types

0
9
0

Year Published

2014
2014
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 12 publications
(9 citation statements)
references
References 7 publications
0
9
0
Order By: Relevance
“…However, there is good evidence that the ability condition on moral responsibility is not intuitively correct and that there are intuitive exceptions. Several philosophers have offered counterexamples demonstrating that it is sometimes intuitively correct to ascribe a moral responsibility to agents who lacks the ability to fulfill them (Graham 2011;Ryan 2003;Sinnott-Armstrong 1984;Spencer 2013). Perhaps the most well-known set of counterexamples against the condition from Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (1984) involve protagonists who limit their own ability to act in order to avoid fulfilling a promise:…”
Section: The Ability Condition On Moral Responsibilitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However, there is good evidence that the ability condition on moral responsibility is not intuitively correct and that there are intuitive exceptions. Several philosophers have offered counterexamples demonstrating that it is sometimes intuitively correct to ascribe a moral responsibility to agents who lacks the ability to fulfill them (Graham 2011;Ryan 2003;Sinnott-Armstrong 1984;Spencer 2013). Perhaps the most well-known set of counterexamples against the condition from Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (1984) involve protagonists who limit their own ability to act in order to avoid fulfilling a promise:…”
Section: The Ability Condition On Moral Responsibilitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Contemporary philosophers widely endorse various versions of OIC concerning what one is obliged, ought, or has duties to do when one is unable to do it [ 10 21 ]. The principle is also frequently invoked in debates in moral philosophy over the relationship between moral obligations and alternative possibilities [ 10 , 22 25 ], and the relationship between determinism and free will [ 26 28 ]. OIC is also often invoked in discussions about the possibility of genuine moral dilemmas, such as classic “trolley problem” thought experiments [ 20 , 29 – 32 ].…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However an impressive case has been made in both philosophy and cognitive science that ought implies can is not intuitive. In philosophy, several researchers have offered thought experiments and argued that it is intuitively correct to ascribe moral obligations to agents who lack the ability to fulfill them (Graham 2011;King 2014;Mizrahi 2009;Ryan 2003;Spencer 2013). Similarly, in cognitive science, several independent teams of researchers have provided overwhelming scientific evidence that ought implies can is not an intuitive principle of moral psychology Turri 2014, 2015;Chituc et al 2016;Mizrahi 2015b, a;Turri 2017b, though for further discussion also see Cohen 2018;Kissinger-Knox et al 2018).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%