2010
DOI: 10.1007/s11229-010-9797-0
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The logic of Simpson’s paradox

Abstract: There are three distinct questions associated with Simpson's paradox. (i) Why or in what sense is Simpson's paradox a paradox? (ii) What is the proper analysis of the paradox? (iii) How one should proceed when confronted with a typical case of the paradox? We propose a "formal" answer to the first two questions which, among other things, includes deductive proofs for important theorems regarding Simpson's paradox. Our account contrasts sharply with Pearl's causal (and questionable) account of the first two que… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
21
0

Year Published

2013
2013
2019
2019

Publication Types

Select...
6
3

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 25 publications
(21 citation statements)
references
References 17 publications
0
21
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Simpson's paradox (hereafter SP) has been formally analyzed by mathematicians and statisticians (e.g., Blyth, 1972; Dawid, 1979; Pearl, 1999, 2000; Schield, 1999; Tu et al, 2008; Greenland, 2010; Hernán et al, 2011), its relevance for human inferences studied by psychologists (e.g., Schaller, 1992; Spellman, 1996a,b; Fiedler, 2000, 2008; Curley and Browne, 2001) and conceptually explored by philosophers (e.g., Cartwright, 1979; Otte, 1985; Bandyoapdhyay et al, 2011). However, few works have discussed the practical aspects of SP for empirical science: How might researchers prevent the paradox, recognize it, and deal with it upon detection?…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Simpson's paradox (hereafter SP) has been formally analyzed by mathematicians and statisticians (e.g., Blyth, 1972; Dawid, 1979; Pearl, 1999, 2000; Schield, 1999; Tu et al, 2008; Greenland, 2010; Hernán et al, 2011), its relevance for human inferences studied by psychologists (e.g., Schaller, 1992; Spellman, 1996a,b; Fiedler, 2000, 2008; Curley and Browne, 2001) and conceptually explored by philosophers (e.g., Cartwright, 1979; Otte, 1985; Bandyoapdhyay et al, 2011). However, few works have discussed the practical aspects of SP for empirical science: How might researchers prevent the paradox, recognize it, and deal with it upon detection?…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This detailed insight could not be revealed through average analysis/analysis of fixed effects (ANOVA or regression analysis). 25 Furthermore, the average analysis is prone to measurement errors from Simpson's paradox [37][38][39][40][41] and that by averaging among the study clusters (in this context, high-swellers and low-swellers and their rate of deswelling), other relationships within the data may be masked or reversed. In addition, the mixed model analysis can concurrently investigate the impact of other factors or covariates that might FIGURE 4.…”
Section: Overall Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There have been several investigations examining the nature of the Simpson's paradox including the relationship with causal inferences[29, 30]. Evaluations of these causality interpretations have also been conducted by other investigators [31, 32]. Recommendations to reduce or avoid Simpson's paradox have been suggested, including a detailed checklist for each research process stage[33] and the use of cross-sum ratio rather than the cross-product ratio (odds ratio) based on a 2 × 2 table[34].…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%