2008
DOI: 10.1177/0048393107310877
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Plural Action

Abstract: In this paper, I distinguish three claims, which I label individual intentional autonomy, individual intentional autarky, and intentional individualism. The autonomy claim is that under normal circumstances, each individual's behavior has to be interpreted as his or her own action. The autarky claim is that the intentional interpretation of an individual's behavior has to bottom out in that individual's own volitions, or pro-attitudes. The individualism claim is weaker, arguing that any interpretation of an in… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

1
29
0

Year Published

2010
2010
2018
2018

Publication Types

Select...
5
1
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 36 publications
(30 citation statements)
references
References 17 publications
1
29
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In recent years, however, there has been an increasing focus on the capacity that minded beings have for sharing other types of mental states, such as emotions (cf. von Scheve and Salmela 2014;Schmid 2009) and perceptual experiences (cf. Seemann 2012).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In recent years, however, there has been an increasing focus on the capacity that minded beings have for sharing other types of mental states, such as emotions (cf. von Scheve and Salmela 2014;Schmid 2009) and perceptual experiences (cf. Seemann 2012).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The attempt to understand the weaker standard of intentionality in terms of the stronger standard of intentionality is his cardinal mistake. It is worth pointing out that the move here is that of individualist intentionalism (see Paprzycka 1997;Schmid 2008;. We have a tendency to privilege the individual agent in all our thinking about agency.…”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…shared in a sense that means more than the sharedness of the underlying appraisal pattern, we need to account for the sharing of affective experience. Schmid was the first to address this question head on, exploring whether there is a straightforward sense in which a feeling can be shared (Schmid 2008(Schmid , 2009.…”
Section: Phenomenological Fusion Accountsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…It is not that A feels this sorrow and B feels it also, and moreover that they both know they are feeling it. No, it is a feeling-together.^ (Scheler 2008, 12 f.; translation modified) Taking up another suggestion made by Scheler, Schmid distinguishes two kinds of subject of a conscious state: BThe subject of a conscious state can mean either of the following: a) the subject who has the conscious state in question; b) the subject as who the subject takes himself or herself to have the state in question.^ (Schmid 2009, 77) Schmid's idea is to allow different subjects to take positions a) and b). He claims that this will enable us to develop a straightforward sense of sharing without violating the true intuition expressed in individualism about feelings: BIndividuals can have only their own conscious states, especially feelingsbut this does not answer the question as who those individuals take themselves to have their conscious states … Without doubt, the parents in Scheler's example are two different persons each of whom has his or her own feelings.…”
Section: Phenomenological Fusion Accountsmentioning
confidence: 99%