2020
DOI: 10.1111/cogs.12887
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Pain in the Past and Pleasure in the Future: The Development of Past–Future Preferences for Hedonic Goods

Abstract: It seems self‐evident that people prefer painful experiences to be in the past and pleasurable experiences to lie in the future. Indeed, it has been claimed that, for hedonic goods, this preference is absolute (Sullivan, 2018). Yet very little is known about the extent to which people demonstrate explicit preferences regarding the temporal location of hedonic experiences, about the developmental trajectory of such preferences, and about whether such preferences are impervious to differences in the quantity of … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

2
10
0

Year Published

2022
2022
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
7
1

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 11 publications
(14 citation statements)
references
References 67 publications
2
10
0
Order By: Relevance
“…What advantages might there be to understanding the discrepancies between the ways in which people naively think about time and our scientific understanding of time? One possibility is that this knowledge could potentially help devise strategies to help people to avoid temporal biases, such as valuing events more when they are located in the future rather than the past (Caruso et al., 2008; Caruso et al., 2013; Hoerl et al., 2022), and preferring unpleasant experiences to be located in the past and pleasant experiences in the future (Lee et al., 2020; Parfit, 1984; Sullivan, 2018). Some philosophers have argued that such time biases are irrational and could lead to decisions that ultimately hamper people's well‐being (e.g., Dougherty, 2015; Greene & Sullivan, 2015; Sullivan, 2018).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…What advantages might there be to understanding the discrepancies between the ways in which people naively think about time and our scientific understanding of time? One possibility is that this knowledge could potentially help devise strategies to help people to avoid temporal biases, such as valuing events more when they are located in the future rather than the past (Caruso et al., 2008; Caruso et al., 2013; Hoerl et al., 2022), and preferring unpleasant experiences to be located in the past and pleasant experiences in the future (Lee et al., 2020; Parfit, 1984; Sullivan, 2018). Some philosophers have argued that such time biases are irrational and could lead to decisions that ultimately hamper people's well‐being (e.g., Dougherty, 2015; Greene & Sullivan, 2015; Sullivan, 2018).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Do people also hold an intuitive theory of time ? Although there is a large body of psychological research on, for example, the way people represent time spatially (e.g., Bender & Beller, 2014; Casasanto & Boroditsky, 2008; Tillman et al., 2018), on attitudes toward time (e.g., Caruso et al., 2008; Greene et al., 2021; Lee et al., 2020; Lee et al., 2022; Mello et al., 2013), and on how time is encoded in language (e.g., Boroditsky, 2011; Evans, 2013), there are only the beginnings of empirical research on intuitive beliefs about time. Moreover, what there is by way of research on this issue does not tell us whether people's intuitive beliefs about time can be said to form a theory, and, if they do, whether there is consistency across individuals as regards the elements of that theory.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Yesterday's surgery, if it happened, lasted for X hours; tomorrow's, if it happens, will last for Y hours. When asked, some people prefer to find out that they already had the surgery, even if X >> Y (see Lee et al 2020). Can EDU model this kind of preference?…”
Section: Edu and The Pastmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…A second possible explanation appeals to autobiographical memory. Lee et al (2020) leave open the possibility that the individuals described in the vignette remember the relevant events, while in the vignettes from Greene et al (2021b;forthcoming), the individual is said to temporarily fail to remember whether the event occurred. Since the recollection of a memory can itself be a positive or negative hedonic event, the presence of such memories could play a role in mitigating apparently future-biased preferences.…”
Section: What Empirical Work Reveals About Normative Theorisingmentioning
confidence: 99%