2012
DOI: 10.1016/j.ejpoleco.2011.12.001
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Nudges and norms: On the political economy of soft paternalism

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
51
0
8

Year Published

2015
2015
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 86 publications
(59 citation statements)
references
References 47 publications
0
51
0
8
Order By: Relevance
“…Some people may prefer to eat unhealthy but tasty food over healthy food, or smoke willingly, even when taking into account the risks involved. Because of this hetereogeneity, the libertarian paternalist faces what Nagatsu (2015, this issue) calls the 'objection from coherence' (see also Bovens 2009;Heilmann 2014;Schnellenbach 2012): nudges may push some people towards a behaviour that is not in agreement with their own true preferences. Sunstein (2013) argue that this problem might be mitigated through personalized nudges-that is, nudges that would push agents in different directions, depending on their own preferences.…”
Section: The Restoration Of Preferencesmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Some people may prefer to eat unhealthy but tasty food over healthy food, or smoke willingly, even when taking into account the risks involved. Because of this hetereogeneity, the libertarian paternalist faces what Nagatsu (2015, this issue) calls the 'objection from coherence' (see also Bovens 2009;Heilmann 2014;Schnellenbach 2012): nudges may push some people towards a behaviour that is not in agreement with their own true preferences. Sunstein (2013) argue that this problem might be mitigated through personalized nudges-that is, nudges that would push agents in different directions, depending on their own preferences.…”
Section: The Restoration Of Preferencesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Finally, even the agents who do have such capacities will experience some cognitive or deliberative costs to escape the influence of the nudges (Heilmann 2014): they suffer, so-to-speak, of a Bpsychic tax^ (Loewenstein and O'Donoghue 2006;Schnellenbach 2012). It seems, therefore, that in the best of all cases, libertarian paternalistic nudges will benefit some agents-hopefully a majority of them-but always at the expanse of a minority of them (Bovens 2009;Lecouteux 2015, this issue), if only because of deliberative costs.…”
Section: The Easy Avoidability Of Nudgesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Glaeser (2006) argues with regard to libertarian paternalism that there is no reason to expect politicians or bureaucrats to be able or willing to nudge individuals into the direction of the homo economicus benchmark, even if they had all the information needed. In particular, paternalist planners themselves may suffer from their own availability bias, and focus on issues that are particularly popular at a given point in time (Schnellenbach 2012). …”
Section: Libertarian Paternalismmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Paradoxically, both green nudges -particularly the default -were also judged as 'intrusive to freedom of choice' by majorities in both countries! 53 See, e.g., Bovens (2009), Hausman andWelch (2010), Schnellenbach (2012Schnellenbach ( , 2016. The unclear epistemic foundations of nudging are nicely captured by Smith (2007: 155), stressing the infinite regress involved when possibly cognitively biased policymakers hire 'experts' who are themselves possibly cognitively biased, etc.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%