2012
DOI: 10.1007/s10992-012-9223-9
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Non-classical Metatheory for Non-classical Logics

Abstract: A number of authors have objected to the application of non-classical logic to problems in philosophy on the basis that these non-classical logics are usually characterised by a classical meta-theory. In many cases the problem amounts to more than just a discrepancy; the very phenomena responsible for non-classicality occur in the field of semantics as much as they do elsewhere. The phenomena of higher order vagueness and the revenge liar are just two such examples.The aim of this paper is to show that a large… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
12
0
1

Year Published

2013
2013
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 50 publications
(14 citation statements)
references
References 20 publications
0
12
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…respect of A as ∼∼(Valid(A) → Prov(A)), lifting this terminology to a logic (in particular to Heyting's) when the corresponding property is possessed in respect of all formulas. (Note incidentally that this has nothing to do with the usual 'derivability' vs. 'outright provability' contrast between strong and weak completeness or between the similarly named properties from (Bacon 2013), touched on in the longer notes on Section 2 in the Appendix, headed 'Bacon and others'. ) What the adherent of a weaker logic regards as the apparatus for making finer discriminations in the subject matter than are available to the adherent of the stronger logic, who is faced instead with a proliferation problem: how on earth to respond the requirement to 'deconflate'.…”
Section: Weaken Your Metalogic: Easier Said Than Donementioning
confidence: 99%
“…respect of A as ∼∼(Valid(A) → Prov(A)), lifting this terminology to a logic (in particular to Heyting's) when the corresponding property is possessed in respect of all formulas. (Note incidentally that this has nothing to do with the usual 'derivability' vs. 'outright provability' contrast between strong and weak completeness or between the similarly named properties from (Bacon 2013), touched on in the longer notes on Section 2 in the Appendix, headed 'Bacon and others'. ) What the adherent of a weaker logic regards as the apparatus for making finer discriminations in the subject matter than are available to the adherent of the stronger logic, who is faced instead with a proliferation problem: how on earth to respond the requirement to 'deconflate'.…”
Section: Weaken Your Metalogic: Easier Said Than Donementioning
confidence: 99%
“…So the criticism would apply not just to the nontransitive approach. There are, of course, exceptions; some people do their metatheory in a nonclassical logic (Bacon ; Weber, Badia, and Girard ; Zardini , ). Let us assume that this is the way to go.…”
Section: A Problem With Expressing Admissibilitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However no definition of equivalence in terms of provability will ensure this due to the incompleteness theorems (one can always construct a Gödel sentence which ought to be intersubstitutable with 0 = 0.) 2 A better way to at least characterise the extension of the relation of logical equivalence would be to select a suitable class of models and define logical truth as truth in all models in that class. 3 Of course this helps us little unless we know which models are suitable, and this depends in turn on the prior conception of logical truth we are trying to characterise.…”
Section: Substitutability Of Logical Equivalentsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Alternatively one could run the model theory within a non-classical theory of sets as suggested in [2]. In the former case one can expect 'S is logically true' to behave classically (i.e.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation