1989
DOI: 10.1111/j.2041-6962.1989.tb00505.x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

MUSTN'T WHATEVER IS REFERRED TO EXIST?1

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2005
2005
2013
2013

Publication Types

Select...
3
3
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 22 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 12 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…See Kaplan and , Salmon , Almog , and Smith and in favor of obstinacy. Plumer (), Steinman (), and Stanley (, 567) express reservations about some arguments for obstinacy.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…See Kaplan and , Salmon , Almog , and Smith and in favor of obstinacy. Plumer (), Steinman (), and Stanley (, 567) express reservations about some arguments for obstinacy.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…), Language, Truth, and Logic. Oxford University Press; Murday (2013) 87 Murday(2013), p240 88 Plumer (1989), p7 and p10 89 Branquinho, João (2003). In defense of obstinacy.…”
Section: <{} Not-being-fat>mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There should thus be no question that a statement such as 'Aristotle is a philosopher' would be false or meaningless if we tried to generate that proposition in a time context before Aristotle was born if using the language available to native denizens of that time context. The more interesting question for our purposes would be to ask what happens if we were to generate a proposition from the same sentence uttered 93 Murday (2013), p238 94 Plumer (1989), p513 95 Almog (1986) p220 96 Ibid., p231 at a time context when Aristotle was alive (e.g. the year 340 BC), then evaluated the resultant proposition at a time context before his existence.…”
Section: Gappy Propositions Vs Arguments For Obstinate Rigiditymentioning
confidence: 99%