2016
DOI: 10.1017/s0953820816000091
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Moral Obligation, Self-Interest and the Transitivity Problem

Abstract: Is the relation 'is a morally permissible alternative to' transitive? The answer seems to be a straightforward yes. If Act B is a morally permissible alternative to Act A and Act C is a morally permissible alternative to B then how could C fail to be a morally permissible alternative to A? However, as both Dale Dorsey and Frances Kamm point out, there are cases where this transitivity appears problematic. My aim in this paper is to provide a solution to this problem. I will then investigate two ways in which w… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
18
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
4
3

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 14 publications
(18 citation statements)
references
References 22 publications
(8 reference statements)
0
18
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The justifying reason to keep one's kidney, if it can outweigh the requiring reason to donate, will also strongly favor selfishness(Hurka & Shubert 2012, p. 9). Another objection to our view is that some reasons are purely commendatory-they favor without justifying or requiring(Horgan & Timmons 2010;Archer 2016;Little & Macamara 2017). But this seems to invite odd recombinations.…”
mentioning
confidence: 84%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The justifying reason to keep one's kidney, if it can outweigh the requiring reason to donate, will also strongly favor selfishness(Hurka & Shubert 2012, p. 9). Another objection to our view is that some reasons are purely commendatory-they favor without justifying or requiring(Horgan & Timmons 2010;Archer 2016;Little & Macamara 2017). But this seems to invite odd recombinations.…”
mentioning
confidence: 84%
“…8 and 30).17 Kamm's case is famous because it seems to involve a nontransitivity: you may do nothing rather than save the life (in a pairwise choice), you may save the life rather than keep your promise, but you may not do nothing rather than keep your promise. For discussion, seeArcher (2016),Portmore (2003Portmore ( , pp. 314-6, 2017, andMuñoz (2021c).18 Even if it were obligatory to keep the promise in Kamm's case, OKAY OR NEXT BEST would still wrongly imply that you must save the life if you won't keep the promise.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The leading answer is that the supererogatory act is only better in a respect. Supererogation is favored by one kind of reason, but is opposed by weighty reasons of another kind, which are said to be “justifying” rather than requiring (Archer, 2016; cf. Gert, 2007; Lazar, 2019), “partial” rather than impartial (Parfit, 2011), or “non‐moral” rather than moral (Portmore, 2011; Slote, 1991)—whatever they are, they counterbalance the reasons to supererogate, stopping them from grounding an obligation 4.…”
Section: The Classic Paradox: 2d Solutionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There have been numerous attempts to provide a formal definition of supererogation, to the point where Heyd () suggests that the concept is one “that cannot be captured by a strict formal definition.” Despite Heyd's pessimism, the recent literature on the topic seems to be approaching a consensus on at least two issues concerning how to define supererogation. The first is that supererogatory acts are morally optional , meaning that both their performance and their omission are morally permissible (e.g., Archer, , p. 334; Ferry, ; Horgan & Timmons, , p. 37; Portmore, , p. 91; McElwee, , p. 506).…”
Section: What Is Supererogation?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…An additional problem that I do not have the space to investigate here is raised by Dorsey (, ) who argues that this view generates implausible results when we compare the interaction of moral and non‐moral reasons in a triad of cases. See Archer () and Portmore () for two ways of responding to this problem.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%