1990
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9337.1990.tb00050.x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Logic Without Truth

Abstract: Between the two horns of Jsrgensen's dilemma, the authors opt for that according to which logic deals not only with truth and falsity but also with those concepts not possessing this semantic reference. Notwithstanding the "descriptive" prejudice, deontic logic has gained validity among modal logics. The technical foundation proposed consists in an abstract characterization of logical consequence. By identifying in the abstract notion of consequence the primitive from which to begin, it is possible to define t… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
16
0

Year Published

1999
1999
2018
2018

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 32 publications
(16 citation statements)
references
References 8 publications
0
16
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The role of logic, in this notation, is for providing a syntax with connectives, and we are not as much interested in truth value (even though on occasion it does matter that the negation of a proposition is stated). This is in line with non-alethic logics; see 'Logic Without Truth' by Alchourrón and Martino [2]." [76,'Introduction'].…”
Section: Episodic Formulaementioning
confidence: 62%
“…The role of logic, in this notation, is for providing a syntax with connectives, and we are not as much interested in truth value (even though on occasion it does matter that the negation of a proposition is stated). This is in line with non-alethic logics; see 'Logic Without Truth' by Alchourrón and Martino [2]." [76,'Introduction'].…”
Section: Episodic Formulaementioning
confidence: 62%
“…Philosophers have of course developed several strategies to avoid this unpalatable conclusion. Current approaches to Jørgensen's Dilemma range from the flat denial that deontic logic has anything to do with truth and falsity (e.g., Alchourrón and Martino 1990) 1 to the definition of logical relations between norms in terms of the "rationality" of norm-giving activity (e.g., von Wright 1991), to the claim that sentences occurring in normative reasoning can be true or false either because there is a normative reality to which they can correspond or fail to correspond (e.g., Kalinowski 1972;Walter 1996), or because they are to be interpreted as descriptive sentences about norms (e.g., von Wright 1963).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This result is all the more valuable since the "minimal" sense in which normative propositions are ascribed the capability of being either true or false involves no questionable ontological commitment to the existence of a "world of norms" as opposed to the familiar world of objects and their properties. 1 The position of Alchourrón and Martino (1990) is in fact that any logic, and not merely the logic of normative reasoning, is uniquely concerned with the "abstract" notion of consequence, that is, with consequence understood as a class of operations on a set of sentences in a language, independently from the semantic notions of truth and falsity. The position of Alchourrón and Martino is thus more radical than the widespread opinion (see, e.g., Ross 1968) that deontic logic is not concerned with truth and falsity because its subject is the transmission of "validity" and "invalidity.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…As is well known, the received view is that the laws of logic apply only to statements (or propositions), which can be true or false. On this difficulty, seeRoss (1941);Alchourròn and Martino (1990).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%