2009
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-009-9388-4
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Intuitions are inclinations to believe

Abstract: Advocates of the use of intuitions in philosophy argue that they are treated as evidence because they are evidential. Their opponents agree that they are treated as evidence, but argue that they should not be so used, since they are the wrong kinds of things. In contrast to both, we argue that, despite appearances, intuitions are not treated as evidence in philosophy whether or not they should be. Our positive account is that intuitions are a subclass of inclinations to believe. Our thesis explains why intuiti… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
30
0

Year Published

2013
2013
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 55 publications
(35 citation statements)
references
References 17 publications
0
30
0
Order By: Relevance
“…To support this line, traditionalists often point to important dissimilarities between the way basic evidential states like perceptions and memories function, on the one hand, and the role of TEIJs, on the other hand. For example, as Earlenbaugh and Molyneux () note, basic evidential states serve as evidence both for the subject possessing the psychological state and for others who don’t possess the state but accept the testimony of those who do. If you tell me you see some event that I’m not in a position to see, or that you recall an event that I was not around to witness, then, unless I have reason to doubt you, your reported experiences provide me with a reason to believe that these events are real.…”
Section: The Role Of Teijsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…To support this line, traditionalists often point to important dissimilarities between the way basic evidential states like perceptions and memories function, on the one hand, and the role of TEIJs, on the other hand. For example, as Earlenbaugh and Molyneux () note, basic evidential states serve as evidence both for the subject possessing the psychological state and for others who don’t possess the state but accept the testimony of those who do. If you tell me you see some event that I’m not in a position to see, or that you recall an event that I was not around to witness, then, unless I have reason to doubt you, your reported experiences provide me with a reason to believe that these events are real.…”
Section: The Role Of Teijsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…It is common to take intuitions to be so taken—and it is also this that underlies experimental philosophers' concern with intuitions as evidence—but the matter is not altogether clear cut. Earlenbaugh and Molyneux () have recently argued at length that intuitions are not in fact used as evidence but are instead just inclinations to believe . And in his online review of Ladyman and Ross's Every Thing Must Go (), Cian Dorr () says:
Often, saying “Intuitively, P” is no more than a device for committing oneself to P while signaling that one is not going to provide any further arguments for this claim.
…”
Section: Trends and Intuitionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…If, on the other hand, the claim is that the contents of intuitions are treated as evidence even when they are not believed, then the view appears hopeless. Acting only in good faith, nobody could advance p as evidence unless she also believed it (Earlenbaugh and Molyneux ) . In any case, the propositional view is not the view that, so far as I can tell, is assumed by the majority of the participants in the literature.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Or at least put credence in it. In that case, revise the argument to replace “when they are believed” with “when they are believed to some nonzero degree.” See Earlenbaugh and Molyneux .…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation