2018
DOI: 10.1037/emo0000399
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Effects of incidental emotions on moral dilemma judgments: An analysis using the CNI model.

Abstract: Effects of incidental emotions on moral dilemma judgments have garnered interest because they demonstrate the context-dependent nature of moral decision-making. Six experiments (N = 727) investigated the effects of incidental happiness, sadness, and anger on responses in moral dilemmas that pit the consequences of a given action for the greater good (i.e., utilitarianism) against the consistency of that action with moral norms (i.e., deontology). Using the CNI model of moral decision-making, we further tested … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
58
1

Year Published

2018
2018
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
7
2
1

Relationship

1
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 57 publications
(63 citation statements)
references
References 53 publications
0
58
1
Order By: Relevance
“…More contemporary models, such as Greene's dual-process theory (see, e.g., Greene, 2007;Conway and Gawronski, 2013), rather stress the importance of immediate affective reactions, available cognitive resources, and motivation, that may or may not enable rationalist processing. If emotions such as happiness, sadness, and anger (Gawronski et al, 2018) or other factors such as time pressure (Gawronski and Beer, 2017) or even emotion-related damage in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (Greene, 2007) can influence ethical decision making, it becomes not only a question of whom to invite but also of when to invite them. This also raises the question whether individual differences in trait character strengths-such as the endorsement of bravery or kindness-can influence affective responses and cognitive processing in a similar fashion: for example, a certain degree of perceived similarity between actor and judge may lead to more positive evaluations ("It takes one to know one").…”
Section: Whom Should We Invite To Give Their Rating?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…More contemporary models, such as Greene's dual-process theory (see, e.g., Greene, 2007;Conway and Gawronski, 2013), rather stress the importance of immediate affective reactions, available cognitive resources, and motivation, that may or may not enable rationalist processing. If emotions such as happiness, sadness, and anger (Gawronski et al, 2018) or other factors such as time pressure (Gawronski and Beer, 2017) or even emotion-related damage in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (Greene, 2007) can influence ethical decision making, it becomes not only a question of whom to invite but also of when to invite them. This also raises the question whether individual differences in trait character strengths-such as the endorsement of bravery or kindness-can influence affective responses and cognitive processing in a similar fashion: for example, a certain degree of perceived similarity between actor and judge may lead to more positive evaluations ("It takes one to know one").…”
Section: Whom Should We Invite To Give Their Rating?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…31 Newer research has been better in this respect -cf. Baron, Gürçay, Luce (2018); Gawronski, Conway, Armstrong et al (2018); Reynolds, Conway (2018). 32 There are exceptions to all of these generalizations.…”
Section: Particularities In Emotions and Their Effects Remain Understmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Moreover, since Greene and colleagues (2001) originally reported these findings, re-analyses show that the specific pattern of results they obtained was driven by idiosyncratic stimulus characteristics, and may not be reliable or generalizable (McGuire, Langdon, Coltheart, & Mackenzie, 2009; also see Bago & De Nays, 2019). Neural data linking deontological judgments with emotion processing brain regions may seem more persuasive, but it is simplistic to attribute any one psychological function to 1 Another relevant framework is the Consequences-Norms-Inaction (CNI) model of Garwronski and colleagues (e.g., Gawronski, Armstrong, Conway, Friesdorf, & Hütter, 2017;Gawronski, Conway, Armstrong, Friesdorf, & Hütter, 2018), who directly define deontological judgments in terms of adherence to moral norms. However, these researchers emphasise that their model is descriptive rather than mechanistic, and explicitly allow for the possibility that adherence to moral norms may be driven by the automatic "emotion" processes specified in the DPM (Gawronsky et al, 2018, p. 992).…”
Section: Are Deontological Judgments "Emotional"?mentioning
confidence: 99%