2012
DOI: 10.1017/s1755020312000056
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Conservatively Extending Classical Logic With Transparent Truth

Abstract: This paper shows how to conservatively extend a classical logic with a transparent truth predicate, in the face of the paradoxes that arise as a consequence. All classical inferences are preserved, and indeed extended to the full (truth-involving) vocabulary. However, not all classical metainferences are preserved; in particular, the resulting logical system is nontransitive. Some limits on this nontransitivity are adumbrated, and two proof systems are presented and shown to be sound and complete. (One proof s… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
146
0
8

Year Published

2012
2012
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

3
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 152 publications
(155 citation statements)
references
References 14 publications
1
146
0
8
Order By: Relevance
“…The main difference with Kripke's approach is that we define logical consequence in terms of strict-to-tolerant consequence, that is, a sentence A follows from a set Γ of formulae provided there is no model where all the formulae of Γ take value 1 and where A takes value 0. Like the Strong Kleene definition of consequence (or indeed the LP one, or the tolerant-to-strict), this notion of consequence supports transparency (see [Ripley, 2011] for a proof of this result). One of the essential benefits of this choice, however, which sets it apart from the other schemes, is that if an inference involving a Tfree sentence is classically valid, then it remains STTT-valid for any uniform substitution over the full vocabulary (see [Ripley, 2011]).…”
Section: Stttmentioning
confidence: 60%
See 3 more Smart Citations
“…The main difference with Kripke's approach is that we define logical consequence in terms of strict-to-tolerant consequence, that is, a sentence A follows from a set Γ of formulae provided there is no model where all the formulae of Γ take value 1 and where A takes value 0. Like the Strong Kleene definition of consequence (or indeed the LP one, or the tolerant-to-strict), this notion of consequence supports transparency (see [Ripley, 2011] for a proof of this result). One of the essential benefits of this choice, however, which sets it apart from the other schemes, is that if an inference involving a Tfree sentence is classically valid, then it remains STTT-valid for any uniform substitution over the full vocabulary (see [Ripley, 2011]).…”
Section: Stttmentioning
confidence: 60%
“…Like the Strong Kleene definition of consequence (or indeed the LP one, or the tolerant-to-strict), this notion of consequence supports transparency (see [Ripley, 2011] for a proof of this result). One of the essential benefits of this choice, however, which sets it apart from the other schemes, is that if an inference involving a Tfree sentence is classically valid, then it remains STTT-valid for any uniform substitution over the full vocabulary (see [Ripley, 2011]). One particular consequence of this is the fact that all T -equivalences are STTT-valid.…”
Section: Stttmentioning
confidence: 60%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…7 Ripley (2012Ripley ( , 2013a has further investigated the logic and developed an inferentialist argument against Cut, a version of which is presented in Ripley (THIS VOLUME). An anti-realist nontransitive approach is presented in Tennant (2014), on the basis of ideas first introduced in Tennant (1982Tennant ( , 1987Tennant ( , 1995Tennant ( , 1997.…”
Section: Paradox and Logical Revisionmentioning
confidence: 99%