Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, Volume VII 2015
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198748717.003.0007
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Christian Wolff and Experimental Philosophy

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
7
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
5

Relationship

0
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 21 publications
(7 citation statements)
references
References 4 publications
0
7
0
Order By: Relevance
“…9 Although the terms had varied in meaning since the Middle Ages, in Wolff's time the above sense was firmly established and commonly accepted in the scientific community (Daston, 2011 , p. 86; Park, 2011 ; Pomata, 2011 ). Wolff, who had taught on and written about experimental philosophy since 1709, was of course familiar with it (École, 1979 ; Mühlpfordt, 1992 ; Vanzo, 2015 ; Wolff, 1980a , p. 146). What I wish to bring to light here, however, is the epistemic logic of the experimental experience.…”
Section: Towards a Psychology Of Extraordinary Casesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…9 Although the terms had varied in meaning since the Middle Ages, in Wolff's time the above sense was firmly established and commonly accepted in the scientific community (Daston, 2011 , p. 86; Park, 2011 ; Pomata, 2011 ). Wolff, who had taught on and written about experimental philosophy since 1709, was of course familiar with it (École, 1979 ; Mühlpfordt, 1992 ; Vanzo, 2015 ; Wolff, 1980a , p. 146). What I wish to bring to light here, however, is the epistemic logic of the experimental experience.…”
Section: Towards a Psychology Of Extraordinary Casesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…That experience is used to verify propositions of physics is also evident from Wolff’s account of hypotheses. According to Wolff, hypotheses gain in probability be logically deducing consequences from them and verifying them on the basis of experience (Vanzo 2015 , p. 236). Reimarus adopted a very similar account of hypotheses (Reimarus 1766a , p. 334).…”
Section: Theoretical Virtues Then and Nowmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Lewis White Beck argues that it is this identification of “a priori” with “derived through a valid syllogism” that made the Wolffians believe that “they could get all the advantages of a rationalistic theory of knowledge while still maintaining an empiricistic basis” (Beck 1996 , p. 265). Similarly, Vanzo ( 2015 , pp. 242–244) states that “Wolff’s notion of the a priori is so weak that early modern experimental philosophers could have easily admitted the existence of a priori truths in Wolff’s sense,“ i.e., in the sense of “derived through valid syllogism,” and Favaretti Camposampiero ( 2016 , p. 365) calls Wolff’s notion of the a priori “mild” and “procedural” and notes that it is all but synonymous with “inferential.” Given what he meant by “a priori,” there are no reasons to assume that Wolff’s respect for empirical or experimental inquiry would have weakened his commitment to the demonstrative ideal of science.…”
mentioning
confidence: 94%
“…5 If we turn to Wolff's Deutsche Physik, that is, his dogmatic physics, we see that the propositions that Wolff derived in his experimental physics function as fundamental principles (axioms) of dogmatic physics. Thus, in his account of air in the Deutsche Physik, Wolff specifies the axioms, proved in his experimental physics, that air has weight and that air has an expansive force (C. Wolff [1723] 4 The importance that Wolff assigns to experience in science leads Vanzo (2015) to classify Wolff as an experimental philosopher. However, Vanzo also acknowledges that Wolff adopts a mathematical demonstrative method.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation