2016
DOI: 10.3982/ecta13191
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Backward Induction Foundations of the Shapley Value

Abstract: We present a noncooperative game model of coalitional bargaining, closely based on that of Gul (1989) but solvable by backward induction. In this game, Gul's condition of “value additivity” does not suffice to ensure the existence of a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium that supports the Shapley value, but a related condition—“no positive value-externalities”—does. Multiple equilibria can arise only in the event of ties, and with a mild restriction on tie-break rules these equilibria all support the Shapley value Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

2
6
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
5

Relationship

1
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 11 publications
(8 citation statements)
references
References 6 publications
2
6
0
Order By: Relevance
“…So, the Shapley value, postulated as the expected outcome of rational bargaining, may be seen as progressively more compelling when applied to games that are value-additive and to games with no positive value-externalities. This conclusion corresponds exactly with findings in analyses of noncooperative bargaining models -specifically those of Gul (1989) and McQuillin and Sugden (2016) -that allow for bilateral mergers. In Gul's bargaining model, value-additivity is a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a stationary subgame perfect equilibrium within which players' expectations converge (as a discount factor tends to 1) to the Shapley value, and (McQuillin and Sugden show) no positive value-externalities ensures that there are no other stationary subgame perfect equilibria.…”
Section: Proposition 6 (I) a Solution φ Satisfies On The Sub-class supporting
confidence: 85%
See 4 more Smart Citations
“…So, the Shapley value, postulated as the expected outcome of rational bargaining, may be seen as progressively more compelling when applied to games that are value-additive and to games with no positive value-externalities. This conclusion corresponds exactly with findings in analyses of noncooperative bargaining models -specifically those of Gul (1989) and McQuillin and Sugden (2016) -that allow for bilateral mergers. In Gul's bargaining model, value-additivity is a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a stationary subgame perfect equilibrium within which players' expectations converge (as a discount factor tends to 1) to the Shapley value, and (McQuillin and Sugden show) no positive value-externalities ensures that there are no other stationary subgame perfect equilibria.…”
Section: Proposition 6 (I) a Solution φ Satisfies On The Sub-class supporting
confidence: 85%
“…By Proposition 7, within our merge-externalities approach, the solution ϕ ESV 2 emerges as the analogue, for games in partition function form, to the solution φ Sh for games in characteristic function form. By Proposition 8, and consistent with the result in McQuillin and Sugden (2016), this solution is most defensible as the expected outcome from rational bargaining for games (such as the glove game) in which there are 'no positive value-externalities'.…”
Section: Undominated Merge-threatssupporting
confidence: 70%
See 3 more Smart Citations