2015
DOI: 10.1016/j.langsci.2014.08.003
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

An interactional account of illocutionary practice

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
14
0
1

Year Published

2017
2017
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
3
2
1

Relationship

1
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 48 publications
(15 citation statements)
references
References 12 publications
0
14
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…40 Interpretation of the propositional content of this act requires taking into consideration the fragment of the context that covers common knowledge of participants of the interaction about the subject of the trial. 41 The author of this article directly observed this context due to personal participation in the hearing.…”
Section: Some Other Specific Traits Of Procedural Acts and The Procesmentioning
confidence: 93%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…40 Interpretation of the propositional content of this act requires taking into consideration the fragment of the context that covers common knowledge of participants of the interaction about the subject of the trial. 41 The author of this article directly observed this context due to personal participation in the hearing.…”
Section: Some Other Specific Traits Of Procedural Acts and The Procesmentioning
confidence: 93%
“…In the second dialogue, the defendant's utterance was identified by the court as a motion to permit a document included in the case files, namely, a photograph of a damaged car. 40 Considering the context in which this utterance was formulated, 41 questions identified therein as the verbal form suggests were also justified (e.g. the defendant only wanted to make sure that the photograph is included in the case file).…”
Section: Some Other Specific Traits Of Procedural Acts and The Procesmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…For instance, in uttering (11c), speaker B performs a direct act of making a presumption that not only shifts the burden of proof among the participants in the dialogue, but also invites speaker A either to endorse the proposition that C is honest or to refuse to endorse it and, next, justify his refusal. In other words, the response that B's utterance invites by convention qua a felicitous presumption-where 'by convention' is to be read as 'in accordance with a relevant pattern of verbal interaction' (see Witek 2015aWitek , 2019b-is either A's endorsement of the proposition in question or his refusal to do so followed by an appropriate justification, e.g., A's utterances of (11d) and (11e), respectively. In general, the proponent's successful individual presumption that p (e 2 ) creates the obligation on the part of the respondent to justify his refusal to endorse the proposition that p, whenever he refuses to endorse it, and, at the same time, (e 3 ) invites him to complete one of the conversational sequences: "the proponent's presumption that p followed by the respondent's endorsement of the proposition that p" or "the proponent's presumption that p followed by the respondent's refusal to endorse the proposition that p and his justification of this refusal.…”
Section: Individual Presumptionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In understanding meaning of words there was three meanings point of view, i.e. locutionary, illocutionary and perlocutionary acts (Witek, 2015;Herman, 2015). These meaning represent what word meant to do.…”
Section: B Speech Actsmentioning
confidence: 99%