2014
DOI: 10.1080/15475441.2014.927328
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Ad-hoc Implicature in Preschool Children

Abstract: If a speaker tells us that "some guests were late to the party," we typically infer that not all were. Implicatures, in which an ambiguous statement ("some and possibly all") is strengthened pragmatically (to "some and not all"), are a paradigm case of pragmatic reasoning. Inferences of this sort are difficult for young children, but recent work suggests that this mismatch may stem from issues in understanding the relationship between lexical items such as "some" and "all" rather than broader pragmatic deficit… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

22
165
5

Year Published

2014
2014
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
1
1

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 195 publications
(200 citation statements)
references
References 39 publications
22
165
5
Order By: Relevance
“…As noted, when preschoolers are shown just a single function of a toy, they infer that the toy has only one function, even if the teacher does not explicitly assert that no other functions are present (Bonawitz et al, 2011). Relatedly, children who are asked to choose a face "with glasses" prefer a face with glasses and no hat to a face with glasses and a hat; presumably if the speaker had meant the latter, she would have mentioned the hat (Stiller, Frank, Goodman, 2011). Thus sins of omission are closely related to violations of Gricean Maxim of Quantity, which states that a speaker should be as informative as required in communicative contexts (Grice, 1975;Horn, 1984).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…As noted, when preschoolers are shown just a single function of a toy, they infer that the toy has only one function, even if the teacher does not explicitly assert that no other functions are present (Bonawitz et al, 2011). Relatedly, children who are asked to choose a face "with glasses" prefer a face with glasses and no hat to a face with glasses and a hat; presumably if the speaker had meant the latter, she would have mentioned the hat (Stiller, Frank, Goodman, 2011). Thus sins of omission are closely related to violations of Gricean Maxim of Quantity, which states that a speaker should be as informative as required in communicative contexts (Grice, 1975;Horn, 1984).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…[94] -are central in pragmatic inferences for both adults and children [95][96] and can be derived from the naïve utility calculus. Minimizing utterance length (communication costs) while maximizing information transfer to the listener (communicative rewards) can be seen as optimizing an overall utility function trading off these costs and rewards.…”
Section: Communication and Pedagogymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However, it is not clear that scalar implicatures are as prevalent as this approach would have it (Paris, 1973;Geurts, 2009). The debate between (neo-)Griceanism and defaultism has been the subject of experimental work recently (Breheny et al, 2006;Huang & Snedeker, 2009;Grodner et al, 2010;Stiller et al, 2011), with suggestive but inconclusive results. 4 Conventional implicature Grice (1975) defines two major classes of meaning that are supposed to fall outside of "what is said (in the favored sense)": conversational implicatures, discussed above, and conventional implicatures.…”
Section: Defaultismmentioning
confidence: 99%