The article offers a reconstruction of John Rawls views on political legitimacy, from A Theory of Justice to his late writings on political liberalism. It argues that Rawls had three conceptions of legitimacy, not two as one might expect based on the distinction between his two major works. Its argument is that the most radical change in Rawls’ thinking about legitimacy occurs in ‘Introduction to the Paperback Edition’ and ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’. Here Rawls assumes that there can be a reasonable pluralism not only of comprehensive doctrines, but also of political liberal conceptions of justice. As a consequence, the standard of political legitimacy is no longer specified as sufficient justice relative to justice as fairness, but instead as sufficient justice relative to a family of political conceptions of justice – a family which in turn is animated by an ideal of public reasoning about constitutional matters and matters of basic justice. The article also shows how Rawls’ late ideal of public reason is grounded in the need for legitimate constitutional government.
Should those who represent and govern us be similar to us? Several legal scholars have recently argued that the composition of international courts needs to better reflect the different experiences and social cleavages in society at large and called for measures to ensure increased descriptive representation. The idea is that when the composition of office holders in a governing institution does not "mirror" the distribution of certain descriptive features in the population at large, connected for example to gender, race or ethnicity, it may be justified to introduce policies to increase the presence of these features, such as fixed quotas, or requirements of having at least one person with the feature in question on a ballot or recruitment list.Normative political theorists were for long less enthusiastic about descriptive representation, and emphasized rather the shortcomings of quota thinking and policies (see for example Pennock, 1979, but also Kymlicka, 1995Young, 1997). However, Jane Mansbridge (1999) turned the table with her seminal article "Should Blacks represent Blacks and Women Represent Women? A Contingent 'Yes'". While recognizing many of the potential "costs" of descriptive representation, Mansbridge argued that descriptive representation measures may have "benefits" as well, for example in contexts where there is mistrust between groups, or disbelief in some groups' "ability to rule". This article re-visits Mansbridge's approach in light of recent discussions of women's representation in international courts. Mansbridge develops her arguments with parliaments in mind-do her arguments hold for international courts? Are the costs she lists equally costly,This is an open access article under the terms of the Creat ive Commo ns Attri butio n-NonCo mmerc ial-NoDerivs License, which permits use and distribution in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited, the use is non-commercial and no modifications or adaptations are made.
scite is a Brooklyn-based organization that helps researchers better discover and understand research articles through Smart Citations–citations that display the context of the citation and describe whether the article provides supporting or contrasting evidence. scite is used by students and researchers from around the world and is funded in part by the National Science Foundation and the National Institute on Drug Abuse of the National Institutes of Health.