2001
DOI: 10.1016/s0010-0277(01)00145-7
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Why essences are essential in the psychology of concepts

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
81
1
5

Year Published

2005
2005
2017
2017

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
1

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 175 publications
(87 citation statements)
references
References 20 publications
0
81
1
5
Order By: Relevance
“…In other words, we believe that these effects fall directly out of the concept of a good true self, which is thought to arise from psychological essentialism, the tendency to understand entities in terms of a deeper, unobservable essence (Ahn et al, 2001;Gelman, 2003;Dar-Nimrod & Heine, 2011;Keil, 1989;Medin & Ortony, 1989;Xu, & Rhemtulla, 2005). Just as people show a robust, cross-cultural tendency to posit an unobservable essence for a variety of entities (e.g., Atran, 1993;Brown, 1991;Gil-White, 2001;Hirschfeld, 1998;Sousa, Atran, & Medin, 2002), they appear to posit an unobservable essence of the self, yielding the notion of a 'true self' (for a review, see De Freitas et al, 2016).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In other words, we believe that these effects fall directly out of the concept of a good true self, which is thought to arise from psychological essentialism, the tendency to understand entities in terms of a deeper, unobservable essence (Ahn et al, 2001;Gelman, 2003;Dar-Nimrod & Heine, 2011;Keil, 1989;Medin & Ortony, 1989;Xu, & Rhemtulla, 2005). Just as people show a robust, cross-cultural tendency to posit an unobservable essence for a variety of entities (e.g., Atran, 1993;Brown, 1991;Gil-White, 2001;Hirschfeld, 1998;Sousa, Atran, & Medin, 2002), they appear to posit an unobservable essence of the self, yielding the notion of a 'true self' (for a review, see De Freitas et al, 2016).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…When 3-year-olds are shown a leaf, an insect and a leaf-insect, they believe that the leaf-insect will behave more like an insect than like a leaf, even though it looks more like a leaf (Gelman 2004). Children from such dissimilar cultures as Mesoamerican Mayas (Atran et al 2004) and WestAfrican Yoruba (Ahn et al 2001) hold the belief that superficial changes do not alter a living thingÕs core identity. Lay adults too draw inferences based on taxonomic affiliation, rather than on superficial characteristics, e.g.…”
Section: Essentialism and Humanized Apesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Categorizations of artefacts do not rely on essential features, nor are they stable; instead they depend on the demands of the situation (Sloman and Malt, 2003). Numerous studies have show that different kinds of features are important to natural kind versus artefact categories (see Medin et al, 2000, for a review): essential physical features are important for biological categories (Ahn et al, 2001), and functional features are more important for artefacts. People look for common causes and common effects when constructing categories; membership of a single causal chain is less significant (Ahn, 1999).…”
Section: Concepts Are Explanatorymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…We apply causal reasoning to explain category membership (Ahn, 1999;Ahn et al, 2001;Rehder and Hastie, 2004). For instance, Wisniewski and Medin (1994) found that people learning categories and formulating categorization rules for drawings of people proceeded very differently if they were told that the categories were 'drawn by creative and non-creative children', rather than 'Group 1 and Group 2'.…”
Section: Concepts Are Explanatorymentioning
confidence: 99%