2012
DOI: 10.1007/s00355-012-0655-5
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

When normative and descriptive diverge: how to bridge the difference

Abstract: Revealed preferences are not consistent. Many anomalies have been found in different contexts. This finding leads to a divergence between normative and descriptive analyses. There are several ways of facing this problem. In this paper we argue in favour of debiasing observed choices in such a way that the "true" preferences are discovered. Our procedure is based on quantitative corrections derived from assuming the descriptive validity of prospect theory and the normative validity of expected utility theory. T… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
6
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2019
2019

Publication Types

Select...
5
2

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 14 publications
(7 citation statements)
references
References 52 publications
1
6
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Fortunately, by modelling preferences (over health outcomes) within a reference‐dependent framework such as prospect theory (Tversky & Kahneman, ), RP can be easily resolved. The increasing attention for such reference‐dependent frameworks in health economics (Abellan‐Perpiñan, Bleichrodt, & Pinto‐Prades, ; Attema et al, ; Lipman, Brouwer, & Attema, ; Pinto‐Prades & Abellan‐Perpiñan, ) seeking more accurate descriptive theories is supported by our findings. Although these reference‐dependent theories may be general enough to capture the strong risk aversion demonstrated by a small part of our sample, further investigation to understand how we decide about health under risk is clearly still needed.…”
Section: Resultssupporting
confidence: 79%
“…Fortunately, by modelling preferences (over health outcomes) within a reference‐dependent framework such as prospect theory (Tversky & Kahneman, ), RP can be easily resolved. The increasing attention for such reference‐dependent frameworks in health economics (Abellan‐Perpiñan, Bleichrodt, & Pinto‐Prades, ; Attema et al, ; Lipman, Brouwer, & Attema, ; Pinto‐Prades & Abellan‐Perpiñan, ) seeking more accurate descriptive theories is supported by our findings. Although these reference‐dependent theories may be general enough to capture the strong risk aversion demonstrated by a small part of our sample, further investigation to understand how we decide about health under risk is clearly still needed.…”
Section: Resultssupporting
confidence: 79%
“…However, as our exploratory analyses of within-subject heterogeneity demonstrated, individuals’ loss aversion and utility curvature may depend on the health state used during elicitation. This heterogeneity at the individual level may be problematic for approaches using averages, like median-optimized parameters (e.g., [ 27 ]). When aiming to address PT biases for QALYs [ 28 ], such as loss aversion, at the individual level, our data would suggest that assuming such median loss aversion parameters may misrepresent individuals’ actual preferences and trade-offs.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…A frequently applied approach is to pre-emptively assume a certain degree of loss aversion, utility curvature, and probability weighting in all respondents. 35 In this type of work, average parameters elicited in earlier work (eg, loss aversion coefficients of 2.25) are applied to each individual. Nevertheless, typically large differences in loss aversion, utility curvature, and probability weighting are observed between individuals; that is, not everyone is equally loss averse or weighs probabilities the same way.…”
Section: The Corrective Approach: Rationale and Overview Of Earlier Workmentioning
confidence: 99%