2015
DOI: 10.1016/j.jpubeco.2015.03.003
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

What do normative indices of multidimensional inequality really measure?

Abstract: We argue that normative indices of multidimensional inequality do not only measure a distribution's extent of inequity (i.e., the gaps between the better-off and the worse-off), but also its extent of inefficiency (i.e., the non-realized mutually beneficial exchanges of goods). We provide a decomposition that allows quantifying these two parts of inequality. Exact formulas of the inequity and inefficiency components are provided for a generic class of social welfare functions. The inequity component turns out … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
31
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
4
3
2

Relationship

2
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 40 publications
(31 citation statements)
references
References 35 publications
0
31
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In this approach, inequality is defined as the social welfare gain that could be obtained by optimally redistributing the societal bundle. 19 In a setting with homogeneous preferences, we have argued elsewhere that it is important to decompose this social welfare gain into an equity gain and an efficiency gain, with only the equity gain capturing true inequality (Bosmans et al 2015). We leave the extension to heterogeneous preferences for future work.…”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In this approach, inequality is defined as the social welfare gain that could be obtained by optimally redistributing the societal bundle. 19 In a setting with homogeneous preferences, we have argued elsewhere that it is important to decompose this social welfare gain into an equity gain and an efficiency gain, with only the equity gain capturing true inequality (Bosmans et al 2015). We leave the extension to heterogeneous preferences for future work.…”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Therefore, these principles, which are prominent but controversial in the body of literature (see Bosmans et al . () for a discussion), receive a new ethical underpinning using priority.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Least concave numerical representations of preferences were studied in Debreu (1976) and Kannai (1977). These were later applied to measure risk (Kihlstrom and Mirman (1981)), inequality (Atkinson and Bourguignon (1982), Bosmans, Decancq, and Ooghe (2015)), and poverty (Atkinson (2003)). 17 To preserve interpersonal comparability of the opportunity-equivalent well-being functions, we derive the least joint concave representations of preferences: the transformation ensuring least concavity of the representations is jointly imposed on all individuals.…”
Section: The Opportunity-equivalent Utilitarian Criterionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This transformation ensures that each individual's numerical representations of preferences is concave and, consequently, that society does not endorse regressive transfers. On the measurement of social welfare by the sum of money metrics, see also the characterization by Bosmans, Decancq, and Ooghe (2016). 9 As Arrow (1963, p. 109) wrote, the ordinal informational basis is a grounding feature and key contribution of Bergson's approach: "It is the great merit of Bergson's 1938 paper to have carried the same [ordinalist] principle into the analysis of social welfare.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%