2015
DOI: 10.1016/j.cognition.2015.05.015
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Using instruments to understand argument structure: Evidence for gradient representation

Abstract: The arguments of a verb are commonly assumed to correspond to the event participants specified by the verb. That is, drink has two arguments because drink specifies two participants: someone who drinks and something that gets drunk. This correspondence does not appear to hold, however, in the case of instrumental participants, e.g. John drank the soda with a straw. Verbs such as slice and write have been argued to specify an instrumental participant, even though instruments do not pattern like arguments given … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

3
26
0
1

Year Published

2018
2018
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
9
1

Relationship

1
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 22 publications
(31 citation statements)
references
References 66 publications
3
26
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…Distributional criteria based on this intuition can be used to automatically classify phrases as arguments or adjuncts (e.g., Merlo & Ferrer, ). Linking the distinction between arguments and adjuncts to verb‐bias learning in this way is consistent with evidence that argument status is gradient rather than categorical (Rissman, Rawlins, & Landau, ).…”
Section: Conclusion and Further Challengessupporting
confidence: 79%
“…Distributional criteria based on this intuition can be used to automatically classify phrases as arguments or adjuncts (e.g., Merlo & Ferrer, ). Linking the distinction between arguments and adjuncts to verb‐bias learning in this way is consistent with evidence that argument status is gradient rather than categorical (Rissman, Rawlins, & Landau, ).…”
Section: Conclusion and Further Challengessupporting
confidence: 79%
“…This strategy, however, does not explain the full pattern of results, because it does not extend to the contrast we observe between obligatory and non‐obligatory oblique objects (i.e., the effect of transitivity). Interestingly, processing differences between obligatory and non‐obligatory arguments have been widely demonstrated in environments that do not involve long‐distance dependencies; specifically, in the processing of arguments (obligatory elements) versus adjuncts (non‐obligatory elements) (e.g., Boland, ; Clifton, Speer & Abney, ; Liversedge, Pickering, Branigan, & van Gompel, ; Rissman, Rawlins & Landau, ; Schutze & Gibson, ). It is possible that the effects of case and transitivity indeed arise from two separate processing strategies.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For instance, the correspondence between subjects and agents only seems to hold in what Keenan () calls “basic sentences” (e.g., active sentences are basic; passives are not). For another instance, instruments are critical participants in many events (e.g., knives in slicing events) yet are not reliably expressed as syntactic arguments (e.g., Rissman, Rawlins, & Landau, ; also see He, Wellwood, Lidz, & Williams, ; Wellwood, He, Lidz, & Williams, for discussion on event participant conceptualization). Since children heavily rely on syntax–semantics mappings in early word learning, as discussed in Section 2, cases where the mappings are disrupted would presumably pose a challenge.…”
Section: The Challenge Of Event Nominals: Light Verb Constructions Asmentioning
confidence: 99%