2008
DOI: 10.1007/s10441-008-9059-4
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Typology Reconfigured: From the Metaphysics of Essentialism to the Epistemology of Representation

Abstract: The goal of this paper is to encourage a reconfiguration of the discussion about typology in biology away from the metaphysics of essentialism and toward the epistemology of classifying natural phenomena for the purposes of empirical inquiry. First, I briefly review arguments concerning 'typological thinking', essentialism, species, and natural kinds, highlighting their predominantly metaphysical nature. Second, I use a distinction between the aims, strategies, and tactics of science to suggest how a shift fro… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
39
0

Year Published

2010
2010
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
6
4

Relationship

1
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 56 publications
(43 citation statements)
references
References 71 publications
0
39
0
Order By: Relevance
“…For instance, construals of biological species as natural kinds with essences focus on some features that are shared among the members of a species (essential properties), thereby inevitably ignoring within-species variation, which must not be neglected on any account of why and how species evolve (Sober 1980 For example, descriptions in developmental biology break the development of a model organism species into normal stages (e.g., molt-to-molt intervals in insects). While this is useful for explaining development, the distinct explanatory aim of accounting for the evolution of development may require a different representational framework because developmental biology's normal stages obscure natural variation in development, phenotypic plasticity, and the way in which developmental stages are created and transformed in evolution (Love 2009(Love , 2010. Explaining the development of a species and explaining the evolution of this species's development are two different explanatory aims about the same empirical object, and different representations of this object are needed to meet the respective aims.…”
Section: Idealization and Explanatory Aimsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For instance, construals of biological species as natural kinds with essences focus on some features that are shared among the members of a species (essential properties), thereby inevitably ignoring within-species variation, which must not be neglected on any account of why and how species evolve (Sober 1980 For example, descriptions in developmental biology break the development of a model organism species into normal stages (e.g., molt-to-molt intervals in insects). While this is useful for explaining development, the distinct explanatory aim of accounting for the evolution of development may require a different representational framework because developmental biology's normal stages obscure natural variation in development, phenotypic plasticity, and the way in which developmental stages are created and transformed in evolution (Love 2009(Love , 2010. Explaining the development of a species and explaining the evolution of this species's development are two different explanatory aims about the same empirical object, and different representations of this object are needed to meet the respective aims.…”
Section: Idealization and Explanatory Aimsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Because attempting to define any particular module with a specific set of genetic elements has proven an unfruitful endeavour, the focus has largely shifted to conceptualising these modules as centres of generative, rather than genetic specificity (Rieppel 2005;Love 2009;Brigdandt 2009). For while it"s undeniable that tracing the particularities of repeated genetic architectural themes throughout evolutionary time has led to incredibly important insights in establishing molecular-based phylogenetic lineages, the aforementioned phenomenon of degenerative robustness ensures the existence of multiple variations in the regulatory architecture responsible for the production of a single, specific morphological structure.…”
Section: This Ismentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The now classic paragon of this is Owen"s (1848) own -that of the tetrapod limb which, although performing a variety of distinct functions in its multiple instances throughout evolutionary history, is readily identifiable in innumerable species despite its specific generative competency being developmentally anchored in a wide variety of diverse underlying GRNs throughout those instances (Zuniga 2015). 5 Due to the co-variational disconnect between the mechanistic composition and the morphological product of these modules, it has been increasingly conceptually advantageous to functionally individuate them with respect to their generatively specific end-states -that is, according to their generative capacities in establishing structurally specific morphospaces, the varied permutations of which represent species-specific instances of their respective homologues (Rieppel 2005;Brigandt 2007;Love 2009;Wagner 2014). Individuating the modules which are causally responsible for homologues functionally allows them to feature in higher-order explanations of developmental phenomena, ones which operate at a higher "causality horizon" (Salazar-Ciudad & Jernvall 2013), or at explanatory levels "above" the workings 3 It may even be the case, as has recently been argued, that the generative robustness inherent in developmental systems is in fact a necessary requirement for their ability to evolve.…”
Section: Why Might Biology Require a Process Ontology?mentioning
confidence: 99%