2007
DOI: 10.1007/s10539-007-9089-3
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Typology now: homology and developmental constraints explain evolvability

Abstract: By linking the concepts of homology and morphological organization to evolvability, this paper attempts to 1) bridge the gap between developmental and phylogenetic approaches to homology and to 2) show that developmental constraints and natural selection are compatible and in fact complementary. I conceive of a homologue as a unit of morphological evolvability, i.e., as a part of an organism that can exhibit heritable phenotypic variation independently of the organism's other homologues. An account of homology… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
94
0
11

Year Published

2009
2009
2017
2017

Publication Types

Select...
7
2

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 124 publications
(105 citation statements)
references
References 58 publications
(54 reference statements)
0
94
0
11
Order By: Relevance
“…5 But this principle, which has been endorsed by some philosophers, is not widely accepted in the sciences, especially the special sciences where individuation according to relational or extrinsic properties, including historical or etiological properties, is commonplace. Phylogenetic taxonomy is largely etiological and biological categories are often characterized by "homology thinking," which is based on historical descent or etiology (Ereshefsky 2007;Brigandt 2007). Moreover, there are other bona fide scientific kinds outside biology that are distinguished, at least in part, on the basis of relational or etiological properties (e.g.…”
Section: Objections and Repliesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…5 But this principle, which has been endorsed by some philosophers, is not widely accepted in the sciences, especially the special sciences where individuation according to relational or extrinsic properties, including historical or etiological properties, is commonplace. Phylogenetic taxonomy is largely etiological and biological categories are often characterized by "homology thinking," which is based on historical descent or etiology (Ereshefsky 2007;Brigandt 2007). Moreover, there are other bona fide scientific kinds outside biology that are distinguished, at least in part, on the basis of relational or etiological properties (e.g.…”
Section: Objections and Repliesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…These modular sub-systems might be considered central (in the aforementioned sense) to an evo-devo ontology on account of their being ontogenically explanatory with respect to the most contemporarily important "units" of evolutionhomologues, discrete morphological features whose broad phenotypic similarity among their various instances is underwritten by shared structural-cum-causal developmental mechanisms which exhibit a traceable phylogenetic lineage. 2 For if the evolutionary process can be conceived as the successive propagation and progression of homologue variation and canalisation, then these highly integrated genetic regulatory networks (GRNs) embedded in the "bottleneck" of ontogenesis (Galis & Metz 2001;Kalinka et al 2010), in virtue of their exerting downstream spatial and temporal regulatory control via the production of transcription factors whose patterns of expression causally specify the particularised developmental pathways of those morphological structures, are surely prime candidates for being the "real players" in an adequate evo-devo ontology (Brandon 1999;Brigandt 2007;McCune & Schimenti 2012;Wagner 2014).…”
Section: Why Might Biology Require a Process Ontology?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The reverse situation is that some traits are uncorrelated and thus one can be modified by natural selection without impacting other traits and diminishing their fitness contribution. Even traits on different levels of organismal organization, such as developmental processes and morphological structures, can evolve independently of each other (Brigandt 2007). It is the particular mechanism of development that explains how among organisms of a species functional morphological variation can be generated, how complex traits can change in an integrated fashion, and how some traits can vary and evolve independently of each other.…”
Section: Evolutionary Developmental Biology: Integrative and Diversementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Despite the presence of such close functional and developmental connections among levels, features on different levels can evolve independently of each other. There are many instances in which a gene is involved in different developmental pathways and the formation of different morphological structures in different species, and, conversely, where the same, homologous structure develops by means of different developmental processes, from different tissues, or by the involvement of different genes in different species (Brigandt 2007;Brigandt and Griffiths 2007;Wagner and Misof 1993). A case in point is digit identity in the bird forelimb.…”
Section: How Mechanisms Adaptively React To Modification: Robustnessmentioning
confidence: 99%