1986
DOI: 10.1093/aristoteliansupp/60.1.137
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Thought without Representation

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
3
1
1

Citation Types

1
107
0
19

Year Published

1999
1999
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
4
3
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 231 publications
(134 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
1
107
0
19
Order By: Relevance
“…I will use a case drawn from the literature on unarticulated constituents inspired by Perry (1986); the case itself is adapted from Recanati (2002). There is a large literature on the theoretical implications of this sort of example which I will not try to summarise (Bach 1994;Taylor 2001;Martí 2006Martí , 2015Borg 2005;Cappelen and Lepore 2007;Sennet 2008;Recanati 2007;Sennet 2011).…”
Section: Transparency Of Structurementioning
confidence: 99%
“…I will use a case drawn from the literature on unarticulated constituents inspired by Perry (1986); the case itself is adapted from Recanati (2002). There is a large literature on the theoretical implications of this sort of example which I will not try to summarise (Bach 1994;Taylor 2001;Martí 2006Martí , 2015Borg 2005;Cappelen and Lepore 2007;Sennet 2008;Recanati 2007;Sennet 2011).…”
Section: Transparency Of Structurementioning
confidence: 99%
“…9 Following forerunners such as Loar (1976), Lewis (1979), Chisholm (1981, Sosa (1983) and Perry (1986), a number of contemporary philosophers of language and mind -among whom Egan (2006aEgan ( , 2006b); Recanati (2007aRecanati ( , 2007bRecanati ( , 2010Recanati ( , 2012; Stephenson (2007aStephenson ( , 2007bStephenson ( , 2010; Ninan (2008Ninan ( , 2010 10 -use a relativist semantics to redescribe de se thoughts as 'selfless' thoughts, i.e. thoughts that are not really about the subject who entertains them, but that are egocentric in a more essential way.…”
Section: /26mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…(See Bach 1994a,b;Carston 1988Carston , 2002Perry 1986;Récanati 2001Récanati , 2002Searle 1978Searle , 1980Sperber and Wilson 1986;Stainton 2006; and Travis 1985, 1991 Having drawn this contrast between two contextualist tactics (one pressing a claim about the semantics of types containing 'know', the other merely making a claim about variability in speech acts made using 'know'), and having provided a general motivation for believing in pragmatic determinants of what is asserted, let's consider a bit more at length how one tactic might be retained and deployed to good effect, even while the other is given up. The general point is clear enough: the truth-value of the sentence 'Keith knows that the bank is open', assuming its saturated expression meaning in a context has a truth value, does not vary according to context of use; but, given how ubiquitous pragmatic determinants are, what is stated/asserted/claimed using (19) can be expected to have different truth conditions, on different occasions, even though 'know' is no more a context-sensitive word than 'dog' is:…”
Section: Contextualism In Epistemology 125mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Thus there are (and here is the final bit of terminology we'll need) pragmatic determinants of what is asserted/stated/claimed. (See, e.g., Carston 1988Carston , 2002Perry 1986;Récanati 2001Récanati , 2002Searle 1978Searle , 1980Sperber and Wilson 1986. I return to this issue at length below.)…”
Section: Saving the Spirit Of Contextualismmentioning
confidence: 99%