2014
DOI: 10.1037/xge0000025
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The topography of generosity: Asymmetric evaluations of prosocial actions.

Abstract: Prosociality is considered a virtue. Those who care for others are admired, whereas those who care only for themselves are despised. For one's reputation, it pays to be nice. Does it pay to be even nicer? Four experiments assess reputational inferences across the entire range of prosocial outcomes in zero-sum interactions, from completely selfish to completely selfless actions. We observed consistent nonlinear evaluations: Participants evaluated selfish actions more negatively than equitable actions, but they … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
3
1

Citation Types

9
66
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
8
2

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 57 publications
(75 citation statements)
references
References 62 publications
9
66
0
Order By: Relevance
“…One stream of work looks at the differences between time-and money-donations, finding that, relative to moneydonations, appeals for time-donations are more effective (Liu & Aaker, 2008), donors view timedonations more abstractly (Macdonnell & White, 2015), and time-donations are more strongly influenced by social expectations (Lee, Piliavin, & Call, 1999). A separate stream of work looks at third-party evaluations of prosocial actors (e.g., Barasch, Levine, Berman, & Small, 2014;Johnson, 2020;Klein & Epley, 2014;Newman & Cain, 2014). Since prosocial behavior is often motivated by the desire to maintain a good reputation (Griskevicius, Tybur, & van den Bergh, 2010;Sperber & Baumard, 2012), these third-party perceptions are likely to sharply influence donation decisions.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…One stream of work looks at the differences between time-and money-donations, finding that, relative to moneydonations, appeals for time-donations are more effective (Liu & Aaker, 2008), donors view timedonations more abstractly (Macdonnell & White, 2015), and time-donations are more strongly influenced by social expectations (Lee, Piliavin, & Call, 1999). A separate stream of work looks at third-party evaluations of prosocial actors (e.g., Barasch, Levine, Berman, & Small, 2014;Johnson, 2020;Klein & Epley, 2014;Newman & Cain, 2014). Since prosocial behavior is often motivated by the desire to maintain a good reputation (Griskevicius, Tybur, & van den Bergh, 2010;Sperber & Baumard, 2012), these third-party perceptions are likely to sharply influence donation decisions.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The study of praiseworthy and blameworthy acts have proceeded largely independently. Some research has compared moral judgments about blameworthy versus praiseworthy acts, documenting both symmetries (e.g., De Freitas & Johnson, 2018;Gray & Wegner, 2009;Siegel, Crockett, & Dolan, 2017;Wiltermuth, Monin, & Chow, 2010) and asymmetries (e.g., Bostyn & Roets, 2016;Guglielmo & Malle, 2019;Klein & Epley, 2014;Knobe, 2003;Pizarro, Uhlmann, & Salovey, 2003), and other work has studied the ethicality of morally ambiguous acts that are not clearly blameworthy or praiseworthy (e.g., Levine et al, 2018;Levine & Schweitzer, 2014;Rottman, Kelemen, & Young, 2014). But the majority of this literature has theorized (separately) about the mechanisms underlying judgments about morally negative acts (e.g., Alicke, 1992;Baez et al, 2017;Cushman, 2008;Cushman, Young, & Hauser, 2006;Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009;Guglielmo & Malle, 2017;Haidt, Koller, & Dias, 1993;Inbar, Pizarro, & Cushman, 2012;Niemi & Young, 2016;Paxton, Ungar, & Greene, 2012;Schnall, Haidt, Clore, & Jordan, 2008;Tannenbaum, Uhlmann, & Diermeier, 2011;Tetlock et al, 2000;Young & Saxe, 2011) or positive acts (e.g., Critcher & Dunning, 2011;Johnson, 2018;Johnson & Park, 2019;Line-Healy & Small, 2013;Monin, Sawyer, & Marquez, 2008;Newman & Cain, 2014).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However, they fail to judge unintended, obligation-upholding side effects to be equally praiseworthy (Knobe 2003a;2003b;Leslie et al 2006). People also more readily incorporate the magnitude of the consequences of proscriptive obligations than prescriptive obligations into their judgments of the agent (Gneezy & Epley 2014;Klein & Epley 2014). Together, this research suggests that judgments of proscriptive obligations incorporate factors related to causality, intentionality, and consequences more than do judgments of prescriptive obligations.…”
Section: Notesmentioning
confidence: 86%