2014
DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00440
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The subjective meaning of cognitive architecture: a Marrian analysis

Abstract: Marr famously decomposed cognitive theories into three levels. Newell, Pylyshyn, and Anderson offered parallel decompositions of cognitive architectures, which are psychologically plausible computational formalisms for expressing computational models of cognition. These analyses focused on the objective meaning of each level – how it supports computational models that correspond to cognitive phenomena. This paper develops a complementary analysis of the subjective meaning of each level – how it helps cognitive… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
2

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 9 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 59 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Other kinds of problems are only visible through modeling at a more abstract level that enables broadly generalizable analyses. For instance, uncovering the sources of intractability in a cognitive theory requires a formulation at the computational level of analysis (Marr, 1982;Varma, 2014) which is usually not available or easily obtainable from verbal, or even algorithmic, theories (see Adolfi, Wareham, & van Rooij, 2022;Woensdregt et al, 2021). Similarly, discovering (possibly mistaken) philosophical assumptions can be harder to do from formal models alone than from theories that make their conceptual commitments explicit.…”
Section: Discoverability Of Theoretical Problemsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Other kinds of problems are only visible through modeling at a more abstract level that enables broadly generalizable analyses. For instance, uncovering the sources of intractability in a cognitive theory requires a formulation at the computational level of analysis (Marr, 1982;Varma, 2014) which is usually not available or easily obtainable from verbal, or even algorithmic, theories (see Adolfi, Wareham, & van Rooij, 2022;Woensdregt et al, 2021). Similarly, discovering (possibly mistaken) philosophical assumptions can be harder to do from formal models alone than from theories that make their conceptual commitments explicit.…”
Section: Discoverability Of Theoretical Problemsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Note that (A, L A )-ABDUCTIVE INFERENCE and (F , L F )-ABDUCTIVE INFERENCE really are two distinct problems; a solution to one does not automatically yield a solution to the other. In one direction this may be obvious: a description L F of a function F need not specify an algorithm A for computing F. To see that the reverse also holds, note that a description L A of an algorithm A may concisely specify a method for computing a function F, but that in itself does not naturally give a short description of F in the explanatory language L F (Bechtel & Shagrir, 2015;Egan, 2017;Varma, 2014).…”
Section: Formalizing Scientific Abductive Inferencementioning
confidence: 99%
“…A further interesting issue is that of the objective vs. subjective meaning of the explanatory levels. Varma ( 2014 ) discusses how Marr's approach focused on the objective meaning of each level—how it supports computational models that correspond to cognitive phenomena—and he develops a complementary analysis of the subjective meaning of each level—how it helps cognitive scientists understand cognition. With the goal of showing that different kinds of explanation arise because we have different kinds of explanatory concerns, a clear case study is proposed by Wilkinson ( 2014 ) by using contrasting theories of delusional misidentification.…”
Section: Plurality Of Levels With and Beyond Marrmentioning
confidence: 99%