1995
DOI: 10.1037/0033-2909.118.2.248
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The social context of reasoning: Conversational inference and rational judgment.

Abstract: Social rules governing communication require the listener to go beyond the information given in a message, contrary to the assumption that rational people should operate only on the information explicitly given in judgment tasks. An attributional model of conversational inference is presented that shows how hearers' message interpretations are guided by their perceptions of the speaker. The model is then applied to the analysis of experiments on reasoning processes in cognitive psychology, developmental psycho… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

4
181
1
4

Year Published

1996
1996
2006
2006

Publication Types

Select...
8
1
1

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 387 publications
(195 citation statements)
references
References 149 publications
4
181
1
4
Order By: Relevance
“…For example, sometimes it is argued that partici- pants construe tasks differently than experimenters (Hilton, 1995;Schwarz, 1996), that many errors are limited to (or at least exacerbated by) the laboratory environment (Anderson, 1990(Anderson, , 1991Klayman & Ha, 1987;McKenzie, 2003McKenzie, , 2004aMcKenzie & Mikkelsen, 2000;McKenzie & Nelson, 2003;Oaksford & Chater, 1994, 2003, and that some purported errors are consistent with an alternative normative standard (Anderson, 1990(Anderson, , 1991Chase, Hertwig, & Gigerenzer, 1998;Gigerenzer, 1991Gigerenzer, , 1996Gigerenzer et al, 1999;McKenzie, 2004a; Sher & McKenzie, in press;Oaksford & Chater, 1994, 2003. In this article, we invoke all of the above arguments to explain robust ''errors'' in covariation assessment.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For example, sometimes it is argued that partici- pants construe tasks differently than experimenters (Hilton, 1995;Schwarz, 1996), that many errors are limited to (or at least exacerbated by) the laboratory environment (Anderson, 1990(Anderson, , 1991Klayman & Ha, 1987;McKenzie, 2003McKenzie, , 2004aMcKenzie & Mikkelsen, 2000;McKenzie & Nelson, 2003;Oaksford & Chater, 1994, 2003, and that some purported errors are consistent with an alternative normative standard (Anderson, 1990(Anderson, , 1991Chase, Hertwig, & Gigerenzer, 1998;Gigerenzer, 1991Gigerenzer, , 1996Gigerenzer et al, 1999;McKenzie, 2004a; Sher & McKenzie, in press;Oaksford & Chater, 1994, 2003. In this article, we invoke all of the above arguments to explain robust ''errors'' in covariation assessment.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…A person with social intelligence might infer that the experimenter would not have made her read this description if it were of no relevance. Grice's theory of conversational maxims, such as relevance, describes these social inference processes that can decode polysemy (Hilton, 1995). Here, content-blind norms are confronted with social intelligence.…”
Section: Polysemy: Not All Probabilities Are Mathematical Probabilitiesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Only in the affirmative is the task valid. For a general presentation of this approach, see Hilton, 1995;Politzer, 1986, in press;Politzer and Macchi, 2000. Let us now review some of the tasks from this viewpoint.…”
Section: The Validity Of the Task: Pragmatic Analysismentioning
confidence: 99%