1984
DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-5914.1984.tb00487.x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The Psychology of Abstraction

Abstract: The problem of concepts began life as a philosophical issue. How is it that we are able to have general concepts, such as DOG or HUMAN, that enable us to think and talk about types of things, and to infer the properties of indefinitely many objects with which we have no direct experience? This cognitive question about our concepts was always raised at some point when philosophers dealt with the problem of universals. For the classical empiricists, indeed, the cognitive problem was the problem of universals, fo… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

1987
1987
2014
2014

Publication Types

Select...
4
2

Relationship

0
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 9 publications
(4 citation statements)
references
References 18 publications
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Those were the conditions under which it makes sense to neglect the differences among stimuli (i.e., to compress them). In our studies, where the differences between stimuli were readily identified, the categorization task did not present the perceptual discrimination problem encountered in Goldstone's paradigm, and the task could be most efficiently performed by, in Goldstone's (1994a) words, “learning to neglect differences along a categorization-relevant dimension” (p. 197; see also Kelley, 1984, for a theoretical prediction of a similar effect). Further research will be required to establish whether these kinds of differences in stimuli and procedure reliably predict whether the categorical perception effect is one of compression, expansion, or both.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 73%
“…Those were the conditions under which it makes sense to neglect the differences among stimuli (i.e., to compress them). In our studies, where the differences between stimuli were readily identified, the categorization task did not present the perceptual discrimination problem encountered in Goldstone's paradigm, and the task could be most efficiently performed by, in Goldstone's (1994a) words, “learning to neglect differences along a categorization-relevant dimension” (p. 197; see also Kelley, 1984, for a theoretical prediction of a similar effect). Further research will be required to establish whether these kinds of differences in stimuli and procedure reliably predict whether the categorical perception effect is one of compression, expansion, or both.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 73%
“…There is a great deal else to be said about how the mental machinery for abstracting from particulars to concepts actually works (see, e.g., Goldstone 1994;Kelley 1984;Livingston et al, in press), including the role of language and culture in the process (cf. Malt 1995), but the basic thrust of such discussions can and should return to a realist framework.…”
Section: Concept Acquisition and Use Occurs In (Real) Contextmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For example, one can assume in this view either that conceptual representations include information about the central tendencies of all attributes displayed by the instances of a category or of only some (unspecified) subset of attributes (typically, those that are most relevant or heavily weighted). The former position (which might be called the prototype approach) argues that concepts represent potential instantiations, whereas the latter (which might be called the duster approach) does not (see alsoKelley & Krueger, 1984;Reed, 1972;.This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%