2009
DOI: 10.1136/jme.2008.026559
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The justificatory power of moral experience

Abstract: A recurrent issue in the vast amount of literature on reasoning models in ethics is the role and nature of moral intuitions. In this paper, we start from the view that people who work and live in a certain moral practice usually possess specific moral wisdom. If we manage to incorporate their moral intuitions in ethical reasoning, we can arrive at judgements and (modest) theories that grasp a moral experience that generally cannot be found outside the practice. Reflective equilibrium (RE) provides a framework … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
6
0

Year Published

2009
2009
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 14 publications
(6 citation statements)
references
References 25 publications
(13 reference statements)
0
6
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Furthermore, especially philosophers working in medical ethics see a risk of logical fallacies and doubt whether attitudes research can be at all helpful for normative reflection. The question is raised whether we can trust in our own and other people's prereflective moral stances, or would it be better if they were replaced by reasoning skills 8 9 which allow for a more thorough dealing with intricate ethical challenges. Other authors argue that ethical reflection should not be based on ‘mere’ attitudes, but that moral actors should be expected to give reasons and rationally explain their moral standpoints instead 10…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Furthermore, especially philosophers working in medical ethics see a risk of logical fallacies and doubt whether attitudes research can be at all helpful for normative reflection. The question is raised whether we can trust in our own and other people's prereflective moral stances, or would it be better if they were replaced by reasoning skills 8 9 which allow for a more thorough dealing with intricate ethical challenges. Other authors argue that ethical reflection should not be based on ‘mere’ attitudes, but that moral actors should be expected to give reasons and rationally explain their moral standpoints instead 10…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…To arrive at a justified output, the argument goes, it is important to start from credible inputs (cf. Van Thiel and Van Delden 2009). And indeed, one of the criteria of the RE conception described in Chap.…”
Section: Making a Selection Of Initial Input Commitmentsmentioning
confidence: 98%
“…Considering Commitments of Others Secondly, on her own, the epistemic agent may only come up with a limited selection of relevant considerations. To broaden the input, the agent should thus also consider the opinions of others, like other researchers, but also of practitioners and of affected parties-for example, in a biomedical context, the commitments of physicians, nurses, and patients (Van Thiel and Van Delden 2009). While the agent does not have to accept the commitments of others at face value, it is important to consider them in order not to overlook aspects of the subject matter that the agent herself might not have access to, or where the agent might be lacking the experience to form commitments.…”
Section: Making One's Own Commitments Explicitmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Wisdom recognises the value of testing a response with others. Wisdom allows individuals to recognise emotion and intuition in analysis (van Thiel & van Delden, 2009) without necessarily privileging either response. A wise approach to ethico-legal analysis acknowledges that a perfect, definitive answer may be illusory.…”
Section: Analysis and Wisdommentioning
confidence: 99%