2013
DOI: 10.1257/aer.103.6.2585
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Surplus Maximization and Optimality

Abstract: I identify assumptions under which policies that maximize expected surplus are Pareto Optimal-even when expected consumer surplus does not even locally represent preferences over price-income lotteries. Besides the oft-made partial equilibrium assumptions that only one price varies, and that income changes do not affect demand, the two other assumptions are that every consumer's indirect utility function is supermodular in price and income; and policies order prices by a single-crossing property. Supermodulari… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

2013
2013
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 9 publications
(4 citation statements)
references
References 28 publications
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…However, in the case of a private good, there may be excess supply at the price set. In development of Weitzman's framework, Laffont (1977) argues that the price control could instead be announced to consumers, who determine the level of output that maximizes their benefit, net of price (see also Schlee, 2013). The information is transmitted to producers, who are assumed to make this level of output (we call this demand‐side price control).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However, in the case of a private good, there may be excess supply at the price set. In development of Weitzman's framework, Laffont (1977) argues that the price control could instead be announced to consumers, who determine the level of output that maximizes their benefit, net of price (see also Schlee, 2013). The information is transmitted to producers, who are assumed to make this level of output (we call this demand‐side price control).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For example,Harberger (1971),Willig (1976),Tirole (1988, pp. 7-13),Weitzman (1988),Vives (1999, chapter 3),Schlee (2013), andHayashi (2017).24 Unfortunately,Khan and Schlee (2017) omit explicit mention of this last assumption.25 The Finetti-Fenchel-Kannai examples highlight how a convex preference relation may not have a concave representation for precisely such plausible preference orderings; seeKannai (1977) for some examples and the antecedent background.26 If the consumer has expected utility preferences and we interpret u as a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility, this fact implies that aversion for wealth risk follows from aversion for consumption risk; seeKreps (2013, Proposition 6.16, p. 136).27 For two continuous real-valued functions f and g on a convex set, D ⊆ R n that represent the same binary relation , g is less concave than f if there is a convex, and strictly increasing, real-valued function T on Range( f ) that is convex with g = T • f .28 For what it is worth, it was reflection on Samuelson's assertions about local concavity of money metric that led us to think about what global properties of concave functions, if any, that it possesses, independently of differentiability and interiority assumptions, and led us thereby to saddlepoints.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The framework has since been adapted to various contexts, including monopoly regulation in a mixed economy and environmental policy, but it has not, to our knowledge, been applied to the labor market. For a recent formulation, see Schlee ().…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%