2013
DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2343496
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Spaces for Agreement: A Theory of Time-Stochastic Dominance

Abstract: Many investments involve both a long time-horizon and risky returns. Making investment decisions thus requires assumptions about time and risk preferences. Such assumptions are frequently contested, particularly in the public sector, and there is no immediate prospect of universal agreement. Motivated by these observations, we develop a theory and method of finding 'spaces for agreement'. These are combinations of classes of discount and utility function, for which one investment dominates another (or 'almost'… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2013
2013
2013
2013

Publication Types

Select...
1

Relationship

1
0

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 1 publication
(3 citation statements)
references
References 37 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Having established rst-order TSD, we can proceed from here either by placing an additional restriction on the discount function, or on the utility function, It is evident from Proposition 2 that restricting the utility function by one degree corresponds to integrating D 1 1 (z, t) once more over the consequence space. If we want to pursue the further case of (v, u) ∈ V 2 × U 2 , representing a riskaverse planner with impatience decreasing over time, then we would integrate D 2 1 (z, t) once more with respect to time (see Dietz and Matei, 2013). Taking this to its logical conclusion, we can generalise TSD to the n th order with respect to time and the m th order with respect to risk.…”
Section: A Primer On Time Dominancementioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Having established rst-order TSD, we can proceed from here either by placing an additional restriction on the discount function, or on the utility function, It is evident from Proposition 2 that restricting the utility function by one degree corresponds to integrating D 1 1 (z, t) once more over the consequence space. If we want to pursue the further case of (v, u) ∈ V 2 × U 2 , representing a riskaverse planner with impatience decreasing over time, then we would integrate D 2 1 (z, t) once more with respect to time (see Dietz and Matei, 2013). Taking this to its logical conclusion, we can generalise TSD to the n th order with respect to time and the m th order with respect to risk.…”
Section: A Primer On Time Dominancementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Similarly, bounding the ratio of u (z) or u (z) amounts to restricting u (z) or u (z) respectively, such that extreme concavity (risk aversion) or convexity (risk seeking) of u(z) is ruled out, as are large changes in prudence with respect to z. Dietz and Matei (2013)…”
Section: A Primer On Time Dominancementioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation