The platform will undergo maintenance on Sep 14 at about 7:45 AM EST and will be unavailable for approximately 2 hours.
2009
DOI: 10.1016/j.jmp.2009.01.007
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Quantum mechanics and violations of the sure-thing principle: The use of probability interference and other concepts

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
4
1

Citation Types

2
78
0
1

Year Published

2011
2011
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
5
4

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 146 publications
(81 citation statements)
references
References 30 publications
2
78
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…For instance, quantum-like models of judgments have been proposed to account for order effect, i. e. when the answers given to two questions depend on the order of presentation of these questions (Atmanspacher and Römer 2012;Busemeyer and Bruza 2012;Wang and Busemeyer 2013;Wang et al 2014); for the violation of the sure thing principle, which states that if an agent prefers choosing action A-B under a specific state of the world and also prefers choosing A-B in the complementary state, then she should choose A over B regardless of the state of the world (Busemeyer et al 2006a, b;Busemeyer and Wang 2007;Khrennikov and Haven 2009; for Ellsberg's paradox (Ellsberg 1961) more specifically, cf. Aerts et al 2011Aerts et al , 2014Aerts and Sozzo 2013;for Allais' paradox (Allais 1953), cf.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…For instance, quantum-like models of judgments have been proposed to account for order effect, i. e. when the answers given to two questions depend on the order of presentation of these questions (Atmanspacher and Römer 2012;Busemeyer and Bruza 2012;Wang and Busemeyer 2013;Wang et al 2014); for the violation of the sure thing principle, which states that if an agent prefers choosing action A-B under a specific state of the world and also prefers choosing A-B in the complementary state, then she should choose A over B regardless of the state of the world (Busemeyer et al 2006a, b;Busemeyer and Wang 2007;Khrennikov and Haven 2009; for Ellsberg's paradox (Ellsberg 1961) more specifically, cf. Aerts et al 2011Aerts et al , 2014Aerts and Sozzo 2013;for Allais' paradox (Allais 1953), cf.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Aerts et al 2011Aerts et al , 2014Aerts and Sozzo 2013;for Allais' paradox (Allais 1953), cf. Khrennikov and Haven 2009;Yukalov and Sornette 2010;Aerts et al 2011); for asymmetry judgments in similarity, i.e. that "A is like B" is not equivalent to "B is like A" ; for paradoxical strategies in game theory such as in the prisoner's dilemma (Piotrowski and Stadkowski 2003;Landsburg 2004;Pothos and Busemeyer 2009;Brandenburger 2010).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…2009Fichtner et al 2008;Khrennikov and Haven 2009;Cheon and Takahashi 2010). The notion of a quantum-like model was invented (Khrennikov 2003) to distinguish models in which information processing can be formally described by the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics (QM) from really quantum physical models-models which are based on physical carriers of information (Penrose 1989(Penrose , 1994Homeroff 1994).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Additionally, this vector space representation does not obey to the distributive axiom of Boolean logic and to the law of total probability. This enables the construction of more general models that can mathematically explain cognitive phenomena such as conjunction/disjunction errors Franco, 2009) or violations of the Sure Thing Principle (Pothos and Busemeyer, 2009;Khrennikov and Haven, 2009). …”
Section: Thementioning
confidence: 99%