1998
DOI: 10.1075/pc.6.1-2.05gun
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Quantity implicatures in reference understanding

Abstract: Gundel, Hedberg and Zacharski (1993) propose a framework whereby different referring forms conventionally signal different cognitive statuses on an implica-tional 'givenness hierarchy'. Interaction of the hierarchy with Grice's Maxim of Quantity gives rise to scalar implicatures which further constrain the choice among forms and their interpretations when necessary conditions for more than one form are met. Wilson (1992) and Matsui (1995) show that reference assignment for NPs introduced by the definite articl… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2001
2001
2018
2018

Publication Types

Select...
7
1

Relationship

2
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 33 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In some cases, the second part of Grice's Quantity Maxim (don't make your contribution more informative than required) blocks the implicature that the cognitive status encoded by a stronger form is not met. Thus, as discussed in Gundel, Hedberg and Zacharski (1993) and Gundel and Mulkern (1998), the definite article doesn't implicate non-familiarity. Since signaling that the addressee can uniquely identify the referent is usually sufficient to allow her to interpret it, given the encoded descriptive content and Relevance-driven pragmatic inferences (Matsui 1992, Sperber and Wilson 1995, Wilson 1992, the definite article typically provides sufficient information about cognitive status, and an explicit signal of familiarity (such a demonstrative determiner) is usually unnecessary.…”
mentioning
confidence: 93%
“…In some cases, the second part of Grice's Quantity Maxim (don't make your contribution more informative than required) blocks the implicature that the cognitive status encoded by a stronger form is not met. Thus, as discussed in Gundel, Hedberg and Zacharski (1993) and Gundel and Mulkern (1998), the definite article doesn't implicate non-familiarity. Since signaling that the addressee can uniquely identify the referent is usually sufficient to allow her to interpret it, given the encoded descriptive content and Relevance-driven pragmatic inferences (Matsui 1992, Sperber and Wilson 1995, Wilson 1992, the definite article typically provides sufficient information about cognitive status, and an explicit signal of familiarity (such a demonstrative determiner) is usually unnecessary.…”
mentioning
confidence: 93%
“…Such facts follow from interaction of the Givenness Hierarchy with general pragmatic principles involved in language production and understanding (see Grice 1975, Sperber and Wilson 1986195). The implicational nature of the GH gives rise to 'scalar implicatures', in the sense of Horn (1972), which further restrict the distribution and interpretation of referring forms (see Gundel, et al 1993, Gundel andMulkern 1998). With this background, Gundel, Hedberg and Zacharski propose that the possibility of reference with personal pronouns versus demonstratives depends on the cognitive status of the referent.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Such facts follow from interaction of the Givenness Hierarchy with general pragmatic principles involved in language production and understanding (see Grice 1975, Sperber and Wilson 1986195). The implicational nature of the GH gives rise to 'scalar implicatures', in the sense of Horn (1972), which further restrict the distribution and interpretation of referring forms (see Gundel, et al 1993, Gundel andMulkern 1998).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%