1992
DOI: 10.1086/261836
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Quadratic Social Welfare Functions

Abstract: has provided an intriguing argument that social welfare can be expressed as a weighted sum of individual utilities. His theorem has been criticized on the grounds that a central axiom, that social preference satisfies the independence axiom, has the morally unacceptable implication that the process of choice and considerations of ex ante fairness are of no importance. This paper presents a variation of Harsanyi's theorem in which the axioms are compatible with a concern for ex ante fairness. The implied mathem… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

2
70
0

Year Published

1994
1994
2018
2018

Publication Types

Select...
5
4
1

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 106 publications
(72 citation statements)
references
References 17 publications
2
70
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Therefore, the proof holds true for any social welfare function that respects SOSD. For example, maximin (Rawls (2009)) and leximin (Sen (1977)) social preferences, which put all their weight on the worse-off members of society, and the quadratic social welfare function (Epstein and Segal (1992)), which maximizes a mean-variance value function of the interim utilities, all respect SOSD.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Therefore, the proof holds true for any social welfare function that respects SOSD. For example, maximin (Rawls (2009)) and leximin (Sen (1977)) social preferences, which put all their weight on the worse-off members of society, and the quadratic social welfare function (Epstein and Segal (1992)), which maximizes a mean-variance value function of the interim utilities, all respect SOSD.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…To comply with Diamond's (1967) thesis that ex ante inequality matters and that it is normatively inappropriate to require that society and individuals abide by the same decision rule, Epstein and Segal (1992) drop the assumption of expected social utility and propose in the context of risk an axiom which captures a social preference for randomization: If society is indifferent between prospect u and prospect v, but some individuals strictly prefer u to v and some other individuals strictly prefer v to u, then any prospect that is a strictly convex combination of u and v should be strictly preferred to u. They also introduce an axiom of mixture symmetry, which prescribes that if society is indifferent between two prospects, then any mixture is socially indifferent to its symmetric counterpart.…”
Section: Related Literaturementioning
confidence: 99%
“…First, the assumptions of expected utility and Pareto-efficiency can be weakened and a non-utilitarian social welfare function can be derived that accounts for fairness preferences of the social planner (Epstein and Segal 1992;Kelsey 1994;Wakker and Zank 1999;Grant et al 2006;Zank 2007). However, it is not obvious that a social welfare function should be based on the assumption of non-expected utility evaluation of risky prospects by the social planner.…”
Section: Non-utilitarian Social Welfare Versus All-inclusive Utilitymentioning
confidence: 99%