2001
DOI: 10.1007/978-94-017-1586-7_16
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Principles of Inference and Their Consequences

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

1
21
0

Year Published

2006
2006
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 46 publications
(22 citation statements)
references
References 24 publications
1
21
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Optional stopping, and particularly preferential stopping, can be used to further influence these frequencies. Though previous work has noted that the universal bound does not apply to composite hypotheses-e.g., in statistics (Mayo & Kruse, 2001;Royall, 2000, Rejoinder)-and the initial favoring of the null hypothesis in Bayes factors has been noted before in psychology and statistics (Atkinson, 1978;Matthews, 2011;Rouder et al, 2009), the work presented here provides a more thorough and general investigation of these findings, showing explicitly how they are related to violations of the assumptions of the universal bound. In particular, the present work demonstrates how large the influence of the choice of stopping rule can be.…”
Section: Discussionsupporting
confidence: 61%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Optional stopping, and particularly preferential stopping, can be used to further influence these frequencies. Though previous work has noted that the universal bound does not apply to composite hypotheses-e.g., in statistics (Mayo & Kruse, 2001;Royall, 2000, Rejoinder)-and the initial favoring of the null hypothesis in Bayes factors has been noted before in psychology and statistics (Atkinson, 1978;Matthews, 2011;Rouder et al, 2009), the work presented here provides a more thorough and general investigation of these findings, showing explicitly how they are related to violations of the assumptions of the universal bound. In particular, the present work demonstrates how large the influence of the choice of stopping rule can be.…”
Section: Discussionsupporting
confidence: 61%
“…As we will show, these assumptions are rarely met in psychology experiments. Indeed the limitations on the universal bound to tests between simple hypotheses has been noted before in the statistics literature (Mayo & Kruse, 2001;Royall, 2000, Rejoinder), but here we investigate the quantitative consequences of the limitations as well as go into greater depth as to where the universal bound remains a good guide. In the following two sections we explore the consequences of preferential stopping when the universal bound's assumptions are not satisfied.…”
Section: Optional Stopping and The Universal Boundmentioning
confidence: 79%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The preceding arguments have dealt with the evidential, post-experimental 6 Note that this does not hold for improper priors where the integral over the probability density is not equal to 1, see Mayo and Kruse 2001. 7 A prima facie counterargument against Bayes factors consists in the "subjectivity" of the prior probabilities in B(H 1 , H 0 , ·). But priors can be reported separately and disentangled from the "impact of the evidence".…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Here, although the inferences (about the criminal, the deflection effect, the table length) were constructed to fit the data, they were deliberately constrained to reflect what is correct, at least approximately. It is the severity, stringency, or probativeness of the test-or lack of it-therefore that should determine if a double use of data is admissible-or so I have argued (Mayo [1991], [1996]; Mayo and Kruse [2001]; Mayo and Cox [2006]). Hitchcock and Sober ([2004]) question whether the severity criterion can perform this job: if it is interpreted so as to sanction the latter cases of reliable double-counting, they think, then it appears also to countenance the former cases of unreliable selection effects.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%