1983
DOI: 10.2307/2026004
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Parthood and Identity Across Time

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
89
0
2

Year Published

2007
2007
2017
2017

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
2

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 273 publications
(92 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
1
89
0
2
Order By: Relevance
“…And according to Absolutism, this is the only fundamental parthood relation. 12 Many have argued that the fundamental parthood relation for material objects is a three-place relation expressed by 'x is a part of y at z', with two slots for material objects and one slot for a time (Thomson 1983, van Inwagen 1990, Koslicki 2008 or a region of space or spacetime (Rea 1998, Hudson 2001, McDaniel 2004, Donnelly 2010 (Sider 2001). But without temporal parts or a privileged present, the most natural option is to hold that the fundamental parthood relation holding between material objects is a more-than-twoplace relation.…”
Section: Second Compromise: the Many-slice Constitution Viewmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…And according to Absolutism, this is the only fundamental parthood relation. 12 Many have argued that the fundamental parthood relation for material objects is a three-place relation expressed by 'x is a part of y at z', with two slots for material objects and one slot for a time (Thomson 1983, van Inwagen 1990, Koslicki 2008 or a region of space or spacetime (Rea 1998, Hudson 2001, McDaniel 2004, Donnelly 2010 (Sider 2001). But without temporal parts or a privileged present, the most natural option is to hold that the fundamental parthood relation holding between material objects is a more-than-twoplace relation.…”
Section: Second Compromise: the Many-slice Constitution Viewmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This means that in an ontology of endurant entities it is insufficient to say of endurants x and y that a certain top-level relation holds between them, because the relations which hold will be different at different points in time (Simons 1987, Lowe 2002. To take this time-dependent character of relations into account we include time instants as a fourth category in our ontology and add a temporal parameter to time-dependent relations (Thomson 1983, Simons 1987. For example, to take the time-dependent character of the parthood and location relations into account, we say that x is a part of y at time t 1 but x is no longer part of y at time t 2 , or that x is located in y at t 1 but is no longer located in y at t 2 .…”
Section: Top-level Categories Of Entities and Relationsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…2.2), are important for geographic data standards. Our work benefits from a long tradition in philosophy which deals with questions of identity and change over time and the semantics of relations such as part-of, subclass-of, and instance-of (Simons 1987, Casati and Varzi 1999, Thomson 1983, and from recent work in knowledge representation, for example, by Guarino et al (Guarino and Welty 2000b,a). This paper contributes to this literature by developing and implementing an axiomatic theory of timedependent spatial relations in a logically rigorous manner in the context of reasoning about geographic information.…”
Section: Appendix: Related Workmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For them, events are essentially different as they occur in time (and thus are often called "occurrents") while objects exist through time (Hacker, 1982), and thus are sometimes called continuants or endurants. For many authors, continuants are thus not to be considered as having a temporal extension (Simons, 1987;Geach, 1972;Thomson, 1983). A lot of objects only have a limited existence, unfortunately, so there must also be an existence function in an ontology of continuants, and a need for a theory of change of these entities.…”
Section: Occurrents Vs Continuants Ontologymentioning
confidence: 99%