1989
DOI: 10.2307/2027108
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

On the Shared Preferences of Two Bayesian Decision Makers

Abstract: This article references the following linked citations. If you are trying to access articles from an off-campus location, you may be required to first logon via your library web site to access JSTOR. Please visit your library's website or contact a librarian to learn about options for remote access to JSTOR.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
57
0

Year Published

2002
2002
2017
2017

Publication Types

Select...
4
2
2

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 98 publications
(57 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
57
0
Order By: Relevance
“…However, our aim is to call into question the assumption that group opinion should be represented by a single probability distribution when precision holds at the level of the individuals. In this effort, we extend a line of argument that uses limitative results concerning aggregation-results demonstrating the impossibility of jointly satisfying a set of formal pooling criteria for precise aggregation methods-as a springboard into IP (Walley, 1982;Seidenfeld et al, 1989). That is, the limitations of precise pooling motivate IP in the sense that certain IP models do satisfy desiderata for "group" opinion that precise models do not.…”
mentioning
confidence: 92%
“…However, our aim is to call into question the assumption that group opinion should be represented by a single probability distribution when precision holds at the level of the individuals. In this effort, we extend a line of argument that uses limitative results concerning aggregation-results demonstrating the impossibility of jointly satisfying a set of formal pooling criteria for precise aggregation methods-as a springboard into IP (Walley, 1982;Seidenfeld et al, 1989). That is, the limitations of precise pooling motivate IP in the sense that certain IP models do satisfy desiderata for "group" opinion that precise models do not.…”
mentioning
confidence: 92%
“…At issue here is whether we should seek consensus in judgments of admissibility or in reasons for judgments of admissibility (probability, utility, etc.) (Seidenfeld et al, 1989). Conditional judgments of admissibility might be seen as a way of walking a line between these two views, but in any case, we can deliver the right results for either view by suitably constraining E.…”
Section: Conditional Choice With a Vacuous Second Tiermentioning
confidence: 99%
“…That account has it that a neutral position with respect to conflicting judgments of a particular type preserves the shared agreements between the parties and introduces no judgments over which there is disagreement (Levi, 1986;Seidenfeld et al, 1989). This way, no relevant questions are begged and further deliberation or inquiry can be undertaken from such a perspective.…”
Section: Conditional Choice With a Vacuous Second Tiermentioning
confidence: 99%
“…First, it may happen that existing beliefs are incomplete or vague [10,11,12], either because there is no resources to spend in their elicitation, or because experts are psychologically unable to specify precise probability values. Second, it may be the case that a group of experts disagrees on probability values, and no compromise can be reached other than the collection of their opinions [13,14]. Another reason to abandon a single probability measure is when one is interested in the robustness of inferences -that is, in evaluating how much inferences can change when probability values are allowed to vary [8,15,16].…”
Section: Risk Knightian Uncertainty and Sets Of Probabilitiesmentioning
confidence: 99%