2019
DOI: 10.1111/phpr.12641
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

On Liking Aesthetic Value

Abstract: We often describe our responses to films, novels, songs, landscapes and other aesthetically valuable objects in affective terms: we "hate" or "love" them, "admire," "enjoy" or "detest" them, or find that they "leave us cold." Most often, we communicate our aesthetic responses in terms of our likes and dislikes. Tradition has a succinct explanation of this way of speaking: aesthetic value is essentially connected to feeling, particularly to a certain kind of liking or pleasure. Is that true? Should we endorse a… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
19
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
7

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 24 publications
(20 citation statements)
references
References 36 publications
(23 reference statements)
0
19
0
Order By: Relevance
“…But it is hard to see how aesthetic objects themselves can be sources of obligation, particularly once we deny that aesthetic objects are bearers of rights or have interests in a non‐metaphorical way, and even Moran registers the objection that “we create an unnecessary air of mystery by speaking of something normative or demanding as issuing from the beautiful itself” (2012, p. 323). One final possibility, therefore, is a primitivist position on which there is no true explanatory value‐claim to be had about how aesthetic value is reason‐giving, just as there is no true explanatory value‐claim about how, say, well‐being is reason‐giving (Ginsborg, 2015; Gorodeisky, 2019a; Shelley, 2011). But such a view would seem to be dialectically unable to defend the existence of aesthetic obligations as opposed to reasons, at least not without supplementation by some of the resources canvassed in this section.…”
Section: The Source Of Aesthetic Obligationsmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…But it is hard to see how aesthetic objects themselves can be sources of obligation, particularly once we deny that aesthetic objects are bearers of rights or have interests in a non‐metaphorical way, and even Moran registers the objection that “we create an unnecessary air of mystery by speaking of something normative or demanding as issuing from the beautiful itself” (2012, p. 323). One final possibility, therefore, is a primitivist position on which there is no true explanatory value‐claim to be had about how aesthetic value is reason‐giving, just as there is no true explanatory value‐claim about how, say, well‐being is reason‐giving (Ginsborg, 2015; Gorodeisky, 2019a; Shelley, 2011). But such a view would seem to be dialectically unable to defend the existence of aesthetic obligations as opposed to reasons, at least not without supplementation by some of the resources canvassed in this section.…”
Section: The Source Of Aesthetic Obligationsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“… For examples of the growing consensus that aesthetic values can provide reasons to act as well as to feel, see Cross (2017b), McGonigal (2017), Hills (2018), King (2018), Kubala (2018, 2020), Lopes (2018, 2019), Nguyen (2019), and Whiting (2020). One notable exception to this trend is the position defended in Gorodeisky and Marcus (2018), Gorodeisky (2019a), and Gorodeisky (2019b), on which aesthetic reasons bear fundamentally on appreciation , understood as a hybrid cognitive‐affective contentful state of pleasurable liking, and only derivatively on action.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…First, it is fast becoming standard among hedonism's critics to flag a distinction between two questions that a complete theory of aesthetic value should answer (Shelley, , p. 1; Lopes, , pp. 41–43, Lopes, ; King, ; Gorodeisky, ; Matherne & Riggle, n.d.; Matherne, n.d.; Peacocke, n.d.). The “demarcation question” asks what makes aesthetic values aesthetic —what distinguishes them from values in other domains?…”
Section: Fault Lines In the Debatementioning
confidence: 99%
“…715–720). His account—which we might well call the Auburn view of aesthetic value (see also Gorodeisky, , §6; Watkins & Shelley, , pp. 349–350)—makes aesthetic value into a normative primitive that cannot be analyzed in terms of further normative concepts.…”
Section: Alternatives To Aesthetic Hedonismmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation