2005
DOI: 10.1017/s0022226704003044
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

On epithets qua attributive anaphors

Abstract: A multiple-proposition theory is proposed, according to which a single utterance can express several distinct propositions. An utterance of “Jon, the idiot, missed the train” expresses the official proposition THAT JON MISSED THE TRAIN and the background proposition THAT JON IS AN IDIOT. It is argued that only the official proposition affects the truth-value of the utterance, while the background proposition(s) may be treated similarly to pragmatic presuppositions. The multiple-proposition theory helps us to d… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
3
1
1

Citation Types

1
10
0
1

Year Published

2007
2007
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
6
1
1

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 48 publications
(12 citation statements)
references
References 10 publications
1
10
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…(3) a. Jon said he would come but the idiot missed the train. (Corazza 2005) b. Right after Chuck agreed to help out, the jerk boarded a plane for Tahiti.…”
Section: Who Gets To Be the Judge?mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…(3) a. Jon said he would come but the idiot missed the train. (Corazza 2005) b. Right after Chuck agreed to help out, the jerk boarded a plane for Tahiti.…”
Section: Who Gets To Be the Judge?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…(Potts 2003) Who thinks Jon is an idiot, who thinks that Chuck is a jerk, and who dislikes Sheila's dog? The first intuition is to interpret the epithets in (3) as speaker-oriented expressions (e.g., Corazza 2005;Potts 2003Potts , 2005; see also predicates of personal taste), such that the speaker of each sentence is the judge. However, does the judge of epithets have to be the speaker?…”
Section: Who Gets To Be the Judge?mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Generally, parenthetical material involves a secondary proposition next to the main proposition; see Corazza (2005), Potts (2007), and De Vries (2009), for instance. An example with an appositive relative clause is (10):…”
Section: Information-structural Featuresmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For instance, "she (herself)" in "Mary thinks that she (herself) is bright" can be considered as a logophoric pronoun insofar as it attributes to Mary a thought she would express by using the pronoun "I". On the contrary, an anti-logophoric pronoun is an anaphoric pronoun that attributes to the referent of the term it is co-indexed with a property the latter would not attribute to him/herself, let alone accept it as a correct characterization of him/herself (see Corazza 2005;Dubinsky & Hamilton 1998). 6 In no way do the authors intend to insult or undermine the former president of the USA.…”
Section: Anti-logophoricitimentioning
confidence: 99%