2008
DOI: 10.1007/s10677-007-9091-5
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Not So Enticing Reasons

Abstract: A common view of the relation between oughts and reasons is that you ought to do something if and only if that is what you have most reason to do. One challenge to this comes from what Jonathan Dancy calls 'enticing reasons.' Dancy argues that enticing reasons never contribute to oughts and that it is false that if the only reasons in play are enticing reasons then you ought to do what you have most reason to do. After explaining how enticing reasons supposedly work and why accepting them may appear attractive… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2009
2009
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
5
1

Relationship

1
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 7 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 4 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…4. See Parfit (2011), Portmore (2011), andRobertson (2008) for examples. Though there might be independent arguments to reject Choice, I will bracket them for the purposes of this paper.…”
Section: A Trading Up Problem For the Rationalist Lovermentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…4. See Parfit (2011), Portmore (2011), andRobertson (2008) for examples. Though there might be independent arguments to reject Choice, I will bracket them for the purposes of this paper.…”
Section: A Trading Up Problem For the Rationalist Lovermentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Second, Robertson (2008) has pointed out that non-requiring reasons are supposed to never play a role in determining deontic verdicts. But they intuitively can once we combine them with other non-requiring reasons.…”
Section: Jollimore On Love's Visionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Dancy 2004, Chap. 2;Broome 2004;Robertson 2008Robertson , 2009 3), in the sense of specifying the action (or range of actions) most strongly favoured by whatever reasons there are in that situation. So, just as 'A is not (morally) permitted to φ' entails that 'A has a (moral) obligation not to φ', we can understand 'permissible' (unmodified) in relation to 'ought' (unmodified) analogously: 'if A is not permitted to φ, then A ought not φ'.…”
Section: The Wide-scope Accountmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…At least given some further claims about the connections between 'ought', 'most reason' and 'a reason'-seeRobertson 2008Robertson , 2009 …”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This is a salutary reminder that reasons, and so the corresponding oughts, need not carry much weight, which is absolutely not to say that they do not carry any weight at all. Thus, to lean on Robertson again, ‘failure to do what you have most reason to do need not be strongly criticisable’ (2008, p. 268). Likewise, to return to the case at hand, doing what you have reason not to do – misapplying an expression perhaps – need not be strongly criticisable (which is not to say that it would not be criticisable at all).…”
Section: The Bearable Lightness Of Meaningmentioning
confidence: 99%