2018
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-018-1041-7
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Model-theoretic semantics and revenge paradoxes

Abstract: Revenge arguments purport to show that any proposed solution to the semantic paradoxes generates new paradoxes that prove that solution to be inadequate. In this paper, I focus on revenge arguments that employ the model-theoretic semantics of a target theory and I argue, contra the current revenge-theoretic wisdom, that they can constitute genuine expressive limitations. I consider the antirevenge strategy elaborated by Field (J Philos Log 32:139-177, 2003; Revenge of the Liar, Oxford University Press, Oxford,… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
4

Relationship

1
3

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 4 publications
(4 citation statements)
references
References 54 publications
(57 reference statements)
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Liar sentences can be used to show that no classical evaluation satisfies NAÏVETÉ. For suppose that a classical evaluation e satisfies NAÏVETÉ, let λ be the sentence ¬Tr( λ ), Leitgeb, & Welch (2003), Halbach & Horsten (2006), Priest (2006), Cieśliński (2007), Field (2008), Beall (2009), Horsten (2009), Zardini (2011), Cobreros, Égré, Ripley, & van Rooij (2013), Field (2013), Nicolai & Rossi (2018), Murzi & Rossi (2019)). Moreover, the analysis of paradoxes has been instrumental to determine the expressive power of theories of truth (see e.g., Ketland (2003), Beall (2006Beall ( , 2007aBeall ( , 2007b, Cook (2007), Field (2007), Leitgeb (2007), Maudlin (2007), Priest (2007), Restall (2007), Scharp (2007), Simmons (2007), Shapiro (2011), Scharp (2013), Rossi (2019)). Finally, the investigation of semantic paradoxes has revealed connections between theories of truth and questions concerning coding, circularity, self-reference, and nonwell-foundedness (see e.g., Yablo (1985), Gaifman (1988), McCarthy (1988), Visser (1989), Gaifman (1992), Yablo (1993), Priest (1997), Yi (1999), Gaifman (2000), Beall (2001),…”
Section: Liar-like Sentencesmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Liar sentences can be used to show that no classical evaluation satisfies NAÏVETÉ. For suppose that a classical evaluation e satisfies NAÏVETÉ, let λ be the sentence ¬Tr( λ ), Leitgeb, & Welch (2003), Halbach & Horsten (2006), Priest (2006), Cieśliński (2007), Field (2008), Beall (2009), Horsten (2009), Zardini (2011), Cobreros, Égré, Ripley, & van Rooij (2013), Field (2013), Nicolai & Rossi (2018), Murzi & Rossi (2019)). Moreover, the analysis of paradoxes has been instrumental to determine the expressive power of theories of truth (see e.g., Ketland (2003), Beall (2006Beall ( , 2007aBeall ( , 2007b, Cook (2007), Field (2007), Leitgeb (2007), Maudlin (2007), Priest (2007), Restall (2007), Scharp (2007), Simmons (2007), Shapiro (2011), Scharp (2013), Rossi (2019)). Finally, the investigation of semantic paradoxes has revealed connections between theories of truth and questions concerning coding, circularity, self-reference, and nonwell-foundedness (see e.g., Yablo (1985), Gaifman (1988), McCarthy (1988), Visser (1989), Gaifman (1992), Yablo (1993), Priest (1997), Yi (1999), Gaifman (2000), Beall (2001),…”
Section: Liar-like Sentencesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…12 See e.g., Priest (2006), Field (2007), Beall (2009). 13 For arguments for the legitimacy of revenge-paradoxical notions, see e.g., Cook (2007), Leitgeb (2007), Scharp (2007Scharp ( , 2013, Rossi (2019), Murzi & Rossi (2019). The indefinite extensibility approach developed by Cook (2007Cook ( , 2009, Cook & Tourville (2016) and Schlenker (2010) does not refrain from interpreting revenge sentences.…”
Section: Revenge Sentencesmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The word cruel contradicts the word kind in meaning and it is not generally accepted that cruel can produce kind, that goodness can produce cruelty. Those two words do not come from the same concept so that this sentence is a paradoxical sentence that contains contradictive meanings, and they are directed against each other (Rossi, 2019).…”
Section: Paradoxical Sentencesmentioning
confidence: 99%