2019
DOI: 10.1111/insr.12355
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Likelihood, Replicability and Robbins' Confidence Sequences

Abstract: The widely claimed replicability crisis in science may lead to revised standards of significance. The customary frequentist confidence intervals, calibrated through hypothetical repetitions of the experiment that is supposed to have produced the data at hand, rely on a feeble concept of replicability. In particular, contradictory conclusions may be reached when a substantial enlargement of the study is undertaken. To redefine statistical confidence in such a way that inferential conclusions are non-contradicto… Show more

Help me understand this report
View preprint versions

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
11
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 10 publications
(11 citation statements)
references
References 30 publications
0
11
0
Order By: Relevance
“…(Molenberghs et al, 2014) and references therein. As such, the time-robust minimax setting nicely fits in recent work promoting always-valid confidence intervals (Howard et al, 2018;Pace and Salvan, 2019) and testing safe under optional continuation (Grünwald, de Heide and Koolen, 2019) as a generic, more robust replacement of traditional testing and confidence.…”
mentioning
confidence: 76%
“…(Molenberghs et al, 2014) and references therein. As such, the time-robust minimax setting nicely fits in recent work promoting always-valid confidence intervals (Howard et al, 2018;Pace and Salvan, 2019) and testing safe under optional continuation (Grünwald, de Heide and Koolen, 2019) as a generic, more robust replacement of traditional testing and confidence.…”
mentioning
confidence: 76%
“…Wagenmakers for any prior of θ under the alternative H 1 . Remarkably, the universal bound is also valid under sequential analyses with optional stopping as soon as a Bayes factor smaller than k is obtained (Robbins (1970); Pace and Salvan (2020)). In contrast, frequentist tests and confidence sets typically have to be adjusted for sequential analyses to guarantee appropriate error rates, and the theory and applicability can become quite involved.…”
Section: Error Control Via the Universal Boundmentioning
confidence: 95%
“…This function satisfies the criteria of Proposition 35. Hence the process M t := s≤t f (X s ) is an S-martingale and we also have (17). Consider the p-value (p t ) given by p t := inf s≤t 1/M s .…”
Section: Necessary and Sufficient Conditions For Sequential Tests (Pr...mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Once more, unfortunately, a naive confidence interval based on the central limit theorem or the bootstrap does not satisfy the desired property. As before, these 'standard' constructions instead satisfy the above property only at fixed data-independent times t. To satisfy property (2), one could employ 'confidence sequences' proposed by Robbins and collaborators like Darling, Siegmund, and Lai [3,18,14], and regaining interest in recent years [17,11]; this is a central topic of this paper and we return to it later. Recently, another set of highly interrelated ideas has been put forward under a variety of names by authors such as Shafer, Vovk, Grünwald, and their collaborators: test martingales [20] (since the test statistics are sometimes martingales), e-values or sequential e-values [23,24] (e for expectation), betting scores [19] (since they have roots in gambling), or safe e-values [9] (safe under optional stopping).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%