A Companion to Experimental Philosophy 2016
DOI: 10.1002/9781118661666.ch23
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Knowledge Judgments in “Gettier” Cases

Help me understand this report
View preprint versions

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
5
1
1

Relationship

2
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 14 publications
(6 citation statements)
references
References 54 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Until recently, the philosophical debate has relied mainly on introspection and social observation to evaluate the behavioral claims, which is typical in Anglophone analytic philosophy (for reviews, see Turri , , ). But introspection and social observation are subject to well‐known limitations (e.g., Lieberman ; Milgram , pp.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Until recently, the philosophical debate has relied mainly on introspection and social observation to evaluate the behavioral claims, which is typical in Anglophone analytic philosophy (for reviews, see Turri , , ). But introspection and social observation are subject to well‐known limitations (e.g., Lieberman ; Milgram , pp.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The experimental evidence that has accumulated since the publication of Weinberg et al's study, however, has not supported the claim of substantial variation in epistemic intuitions (Turri 2016). There have been several failures to replicate the original finding of cultural variation in epistemic intuitions (Machery et al 2017;Seyedsayamdost 2015;Turri 2013), including a study using exactly the same experimental materials as the original Weinberg et al (2001) study but using a substantially larger sample size (Kim and Yuan 2015).…”
Section: Baz's Challenge To "The Prevailing Program"mentioning
confidence: 95%
“…The wider pattern of responses to different types of Gettier cases reported in Blouw et al 2017, Starmans and Friedman (2012) and Turri et al (2015), which include responses to (theoretically) clear cases of knowledge and clear cases of non-knowledge (either cases of false belief, or true beliefs that lack justification) in fact poses a challenge to Baz's contention that the theorist's question (which, in Gettier cases is the question whether the protagonist knows that, e.g., Jill drives an American car) is not "clear" because it lacks a practical point. 11 If the theorist's question lacked a sense, as Baz claims then it should be surprising to see the consistent levels of knowledge-denial in certain kinds of Gettier cases that experimenters have found (around 80%-see Turri 2016, p. 341) as well as the consistent patterns of variation when epistemically significant features of the Gettier cases are varied (see the Appendix for details), and especially the much higher rates of knowledge attribution in theoretically clear cases of knowledge (79-90% in Starmans and Friedman 2012 and Turri et al 2015) than in theoretically clear cases of non-knowledge (8-14% in Friedman 2012 andTurri et al 2015). 12 (All of these experimental studies are described in greater detail in the Appendix.…”
Section: Baz's Challenge To "The Prevailing Program"mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In what follows, I distinguish between Gettier's cases, which I have already discussed, and "Gettier" cases (always with scare quotes). The former come from Gettier's original paper, but the latter are merely a nominal category with no underlying unity (Turri 2016a). For reasons already discussed, no serious study of knowledge judgments would use Gettier's cases because the results could not be meaningfully interpreted.…”
Section: !mentioning
confidence: 99%