2017
DOI: 10.26556/jesp.v8i1.77
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Keep Things in Perspective

Abstract: Objective reasons are given by the facts. Subjective reasons are given by one’s perspective on the facts. Subjective reasons, not objective reasons, determine what it is rational to do. In this paper, I argue against a prominent account of subjective reasons. The problem with that account, I suggest, is that it makes what one has subjective reason to do, and hence what it is rational to do, turn on matters outside or independent of one’s perspective. After explaining and establishing this point, I offer a nove… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
2
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 25 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 29 publications
0
2
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The second background principle driving D3 is the thesis that, in order for a fact p to provide one with (some, sufficient, decisive) reason to Φ, one must have the ability to Φ (Sylvan 2015(Sylvan , 2018 or know how to Φ (Lord 2018: Ch.4). To deny this is to affirm the idea that one can have (some, sufficient, decisive) reason to Φ even though one is unable to or doesn't know 8 Broad factualism is a prominent position in the literature on the normativity of action (Alvarez 2010, Dancy 2000, Kiesewetter 2017, Parfit 2011, Raz 1999, Scanlon 1998, Schroeder 2007, Skorupski 2011, Thomson 2008, and Whiting 2014 and the normativity of belief (Kiesewetter 2017;Littlejohn 2017;Lord 2018;Schroeder 2015;Sylvan 2015Sylvan , 2016Sylvan , 2018and Whiting 2014). how to Φ.…”
Section: D2 Ignorance Excludes Reasons-responsivenessmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The second background principle driving D3 is the thesis that, in order for a fact p to provide one with (some, sufficient, decisive) reason to Φ, one must have the ability to Φ (Sylvan 2015(Sylvan , 2018 or know how to Φ (Lord 2018: Ch.4). To deny this is to affirm the idea that one can have (some, sufficient, decisive) reason to Φ even though one is unable to or doesn't know 8 Broad factualism is a prominent position in the literature on the normativity of action (Alvarez 2010, Dancy 2000, Kiesewetter 2017, Parfit 2011, Raz 1999, Scanlon 1998, Schroeder 2007, Skorupski 2011, Thomson 2008, and Whiting 2014 and the normativity of belief (Kiesewetter 2017;Littlejohn 2017;Lord 2018;Schroeder 2015;Sylvan 2015Sylvan , 2016Sylvan , 2018and Whiting 2014). how to Φ.…”
Section: D2 Ignorance Excludes Reasons-responsivenessmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…3 So for instance you could have a subjective normative reason to drink any nearby gin and even a subjective normative reason to drink the petrol, because you justifiably believe it is gin. 4 From here on out, I will talk just of objective and subjective reasons, but I will be discussing normative reasons, which are the reasons which describe what it is rational for us to do, rather than motivating reasons (the reasons on which we act) or any other sorts of reasons (Whiting 2014).…”
Section: The Epistemic Account Of the Normativity Of Requestsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…70 For this line of criticism, see Kiesewetter,The Normativity of Rationality,[31][32][33] beliefs are themselves rational (of course, this makes the view unsatisfactory as a reductive account of rationality, but this is not Whiting's goal). 71 An alternative strategy is to characterize the idea of apparent reason in terms of the notion of competence, which would be taken as more basic. On Sylvan's view, some consideration is an apparent reason for an agent if she is in a position to competently treat it as a reason.72 In turn, competence in treating considerations as reasons can be understood as a reliable disposition to be guided only by normative reasons, or by reference to the way in which some virtuous or ideal agent would be disposed to respond.73 An agent that recklessly holds the belief that p against all available evidence will not be competently treating p as a reason (her holding that belief would manifest a very unreliable disposition to be guided only by reasons), so p would not be among her apparent reasons and would not make the agent's behavior rational.…”
Section: Rationality and Apparent Reasonsmentioning
confidence: 99%