1992
DOI: 10.1086/293423
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

John Stuart Mill and the Harm of Pornography

Abstract: How to cite TSpace items Always cite the published version, so the author(s) will receive recognition through services that track citation counts, e.g. Scopus. If you need to cite the page number of the author manuscript from TSpace because you cannot access the published version, then cite the TSpace version in addition to the published version using the permanent URI (handle) found on the record page.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
12
0

Year Published

1996
1996
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
3
3
2

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 40 publications
(12 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
12
0
Order By: Relevance
“…For instance, even if the 'stars' of violent pornography consent to their role in its production, society might intervene if it is harmful to other women who do not consent (c.f. Dyzenhaus, 1992;Skipper, 1993;Vernon, 1996).…”
Section: Should All Consensual Harm Be Protected?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For instance, even if the 'stars' of violent pornography consent to their role in its production, society might intervene if it is harmful to other women who do not consent (c.f. Dyzenhaus, 1992;Skipper, 1993;Vernon, 1996).…”
Section: Should All Consensual Harm Be Protected?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The pro‐censorship case argues that this liberal approach endorses metaphysically unjustified “absolute” (McGlynn and Ward , 520), “abstract” (McGlynn and Ward , 339), “ a priori ” (Dyzenhaus b, 546) rights to privacy and free expression and that the liberal approach relies on an impoverished conception of “direct” harm that denies the real harms and injustice of pornographic expression beyond that directly associated with its production (McGlynn and Ward , 503). Once these abstractions are dismissed, those in favor of censorship suggest that liberals can approach questions of free expression and individual liberty on a more contingent, case‐by‐case basis (McGlynn and Ward , 341).…”
Section: The Millian Case For Censorshipmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…It must either be shown to directly cause actual physical violence to others (e.g., murder, rape, assault, battery), on a narrower understanding of "harm"; or to deliberately or negligently violate sufficiently important interests or rights of others, on a broader, interest-based conception of "harm". (For further discussion of these different conceptions of harm to others see e.g., Dyzenhaus 1992, Feinberg 1987 Liberals have traditionally defended a right to pornography on three main grounds. (By the "right to pornography" here, and in what follows, I mean the negative right of consenting adults not to be prevented from making, publishing, exhibiting, distributing and consuming pornography in private).…”
Section: The Traditional Liberal Defence Of a Right To Pornographymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Inspired by more recent feminist arguments against pornography, some have begun to argue that the liberal commitment to protecting individual autonomy, equality, freedom of expression and other liberal values may in fact support a policy that prohibits certain kinds of pornography, rather than the permissive policy liberals have traditionally favoured. (See e.g., Dyzenhaus 1992, Easton 1994: 42-51, Langton 1990, Okin 1987, West 2003.) These theorists do not normally reject the harm principle, broadly understood: They generally agree that the crucial question in determining whether censorship of pornography is justified is whether there is reliable evidence to show that the publication or viewing of pornography by consenting adults causes sufficiently great harm to the significant interests of others.…”
Section: Recent Liberal Dissentmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation